








| |
Relativistic Skepticism in the Zhuangzi
This decade has witnessed a sea change in Zhuangzi interpretations.
In 1983, I wrote, "The interpretation of Zhuangzi is a philosophical scandal."�
Today, a quick electronic literature search for titles or abstracts containing
'Zhuangzi' and either 'skeptic' or 'relativism' produce more hits that one that
excludes them. I trace this development to Graham's discovery decades ago that
the Zhuangzi addressed the questions found in the Mohist Canons and
to his breakthrough reading of the Qiwulun as an "inner dialogue"
with positions posed, considered and then subjected to doubt.
Seeing the Zhuangzi as a work of philosophy reflecting a grasp of a
technical ancient Chinese theory of language undercuts the traditional, dismissive
interpretation classically expressed by Schwartz (1985): "We shall again
begin our account of the historic Chuang-tzu with the mystical vision which
he shares with the Lao-tzu.� Chuang-tzu's constant efforts to describe the indescribable
in many ways simply amplify and enrich what we have already found in the Lao-tzu.
. ." (Schwartz 1985:216-7).
This philosophical shift in interpretive focus is remarkable because the broad
field remains a "polyglot" discipline. Zhuangzi interpreters may
be trained in religion, literature, history, or philosophy. Established interpretations,
stemming from the missionary generations of Sinologists, echo modern religious
themes. [1] An aversion
to Western "linguistic" philosophy still draws many to the study of
Chinese thought. They affectionately search the Chinese dao for a rebuke
to "rigid" Western reason. In Sinological circles, people typically
pronounce 'analytic' with a sneer. 'Relativist', 'skeptic' and even 'logic'
fare little better in Sinological discourse. Even 'philosophical' they typically
use pejoratively.� Exchanging the loveable, comic-strip religious mystic for
a skeptical philosopher has its costs.
Gratifying, then, as the focus on skepticism and relativism are, recent discussion
still reflects a chronic nostalgia for the lost guru and exhibits a lingering
discomfort with philosophy, its issues and approach. Recent writers have challenged
or reformulated the characterization of Zhuangzi as a "relativist skeptic." [2] They typically pose skepticism and insight as
an either-or choice.
I attempt here to defend my classifying familiar arguments and lines of thought
in the Zhuangzi as relativist skepticism against recent accusations that
the interpretation is philosophically incoherent.� Further I will explain how
the Zhuangzi that emerges can satisfy our nostalgic urge to find "guiding
wisdom" in the text. The practical implications lie in the secular social-political
issues that preoccupied classical Chinese philosophers. We can placate the fond
yearning for guidance (though not "spiritual transformation")
from the Zhuangzi while appreciating its philosophical acuity. The
Daoist text does led to political and personal wisdom as well as a careful epistemology
and theory of language.
In section I, I outline a composite case against straightforward reading
of the skeptical passages to which I respond in section II on methodology grounds
and in section III by clarifying the conceptual background of the Zhuangzi
passages. Then, in section IV, I analyze the types of monism, skepticism,
and relativism implied in those passages. Finally in section V, I briefly address
the political role of the relativistic skepticism in the Zhuangzi in
a way that vindicates Daoism as a form of Chinese political liberalism.
Prudent modesty, past experience,
[3] as well as the argument
I will attribute to the Zhuangzi all prompt me to refrain from trying
to characterize the arguments of individual critics of my interpretation. I
will, instead, set out a line of thought that I think captures common
threads of such arguments.� With some variation in detail, I find the arguments
against a relativist or skeptical view of the Zhuangzi have these components.
1.
[Full text coherence] Start with a methodological interpretive principle.� Any
such characterization must coherently explain the entire text of the
Zhuangzi (or at least explain more of it than a rival view).
2.
[Traditional tone] Then characterize the "overall tone" in
more traditional terms, e.g. mystical, inspirational, credulous etc.
3.
[Disabling definition] Invoke a definition or formula of 'skepticism',
'relativism' or both. Usually they tie the definition to what they term as a
'strong', 'extreme', or 'radical' version that is either incoherent on its face
or that makes their joint use incoherent. [4]
4.
[Therapeutic salvation] (Some versions only) Conclude that the skeptical
(or relativist) passages are really only "therapeutic," that
Zhuangzi was not committed to what the passages entail or they do not entail
anything negative about the sage's cognitive achievements. Treat the
passages instead as a recommendation of a way a person should use their
mind to bring about some personal or spiritual transformation, e.g. If we refrain
from judgments or commitments, we will have peace of mind or transcendent wisdom,
etc.
Step 1 and 2 yield the initial motivation to "defang" the skeptical
and relativist passages. Step 3 buttresses this initial motivation with a direct
attack on the coherence of the alleged philosophical position and step 4 completes
the argument that the passages do not indicate a skeptical or relativist Zhuangzi.
In the section II below, I will argue that step 1's full text coherence interpretive
principle is specious. A Chinese philosophical text, like a German, French or
English one, may contain inconsistencies and lack coherence. The theoretically
justifiable role of coherence in interpretation is holistic--it constrains how
we interpret the entire linguistic community, not single authors or texts.
I will argue that this theoretical motivation for coherence justifies our taking
the view of a representative, philosophically informed, contemporaneous reader
of the text, rather than the writer, as the point of interpretive reference.
Avoiding communal incoherence is the sound form of this interpretive
injunction. [5]
In step 2 above, the appeal to the traditional tone begs questions since we
may come see the overall tone quite differently after we have appreciated the
skeptical and relativistic line of reasoning. The "tone" of the text
as a whole is just as subject to interpretive justification as are the skeptical
passages.� Any inconsistency should equally invite dismissing or reinterpreting
the passages with an allegedly mystical tone. Anticipating this answer explains
why anti-skeptics also directly attack the coherence of the philosophical positions
(step 3).
For the disabling definitions in step 3 to do their work (showing skepticism
and relativisism are incoherent), those critics need to justify their disabling
formulations as (a) fitting in the conceptual and philosophical context of the
Zhuangzi arguments and (b) consistent with competent philosophical explication
of these positions. I argue in section III that the disabling definitions fail
on the first count and in section IV that they fail on the second. However,
they do stimulate us to address the kind of skepticism implied by the
various Zhuangzi passages.
In section III , I will set out the relevant conceptual and philosophical context
with which an informed philosophical reader in ancient China should have
read the Zhuangzi. Politically and ethically, that context centers on
disputes about dao (ways of life).� These disputes are set in a tradition
preoccupied with social-political issues and whose main epistemic terms did
not take the familiar, sentential, form characteristic of counterpart
Western theories. That is, if there was skepticism in ancient China, they would
formulate them in terms other than 'belief', 'truth', 'meaning', "propositional
knowledge," or 'reason'.
In section IV , I will offer
an analytical typology of three related positions in Zhuangzi interpretation:
'monism' (a metaphysical commitment), 'skepticism' (an epistemic one) and relativism
(a view of the inferential "dependency" of our commitments). I will
identify the particular types to which the Zhuangzi arguments are committed
given the conceptual and philosophical context. We will find Zhuangzi's
position considerably more subtle and plausible than the formulations offered
in the disabling definitions (step 2) above.
In section V , I will briefly
present the political implication I take the relativistic-skeptical passages
to have. This will be brief because I do not intend to argue that the Zhuangzi
presented this conclusion, but that the text's skepticism argumentatively
supports Chinese liberalism. Numerous other familiar stories and passages clearly
reinforce the liberal tendency.�
Coherence plays a role as a formal principle guiding radical translation. As
Quine (1960) puts it, we select among "translation manuals" for a
language based on the effect the selection has on the total system of beliefs
we attribute to the speakers. The principles of interpretation (charity and
humanity) tell us what virtue of the system of belief counts.�
I had argued [6]
for the principle of humanity and characterized it mainly in terms of coherence.
I argued that 'coherent' was preferable to the principle of Charity's 'true'
as the virtue of other tradition's belief system since it preserves the possibility
of intelligible disagreement between us. Ancient Chinese philosophers can coherently
disagree with us.
The full text coherence objection (above step 1 ) confuses the role
of coherence in applying it to interpreting the philosophies of individuals.
[7] This produces the implausible result that no individual can
be committed to an incoherent philosophical position. That is clearly too strong
a constraint on interpretation. The profound philosophical questions that
have puzzled and exercised great minds over the ages and across cultures are
surely matters on which we can find someone both wrong and intelligible (interpretable).
If some philosopher argued that skepticism was analytically inconsistent, it
would not commit him to the conclusion that Hume was not a skeptic. Obviously,
the inference applies ceteris paribus to Zhuangzi.
Interpretive coherence instructively applies at a different level. The
interpreter is an explanatory theorist and her theory, qua explanation,
should be coherent.� An interpreter�s theory may attribute an incoherent theory
to the author she interprets without herself becoming incoherent.� That invites
a reformulation of the principle of humanity that de-emphasizes coherence of
the text. Let us think of the principle of humanity as a principle of coherently
explainable access to the belief system.
[8] The interpreter's task is to attribute beliefs to which she
can explain the community's access in ways that are coherent with everything
we know.�
Consider a scientific example. One of the puzzles of Chinese thought is Daoist
cosmological reference to 10,000 things (wan wu). It must have been clear to
Chinese thinkers that the number of objects in the world is greater than 10,000.�
Scholars mostly propose to modify the meaning of wan10,000.
They theorize that it just means "myriad" or "a large number"
or "all." An alternative is to modify the meaning of wuthing
arguing that it does not refer to an object in the Western sense, but
to a kind.
Now consider this solution.� As it turns out, modern astronomers say that the
universe does consist of approximately 10,000 mega-objects. The
most stable and persistent objects in the universe are galaxy clusters. They
are objects in the sense that gravity has held them together from relatively
soon after the big bang. Giant gas "clouds" fill these clusters, which
were the first structures to emerge in the universe. Although they change,
they are changing more slowly than are any of the bits that constitute
them.
Presumably, we should not say that the Daoist use of wanwu [10,000 things]
(especially in the famous cosmological passages) refers to galaxy clusters despite
the "fit" between the two descriptions. This interpretation would
make the (apparently widely shared) cosmology of the ancient community true
and satisfy the principle of charity. The objection appropriate for the
principle of humanity is not that the theory of galaxy clusters is incoherent,
but that I cannot tell a plausible, naturalistic story about how ancient Chinese
cosmologists would have access to a belief or theory of galaxy clusters. Coherence
comes in, if at all, in that my story would not be coherent with everything
else I know about them, their sensory apparatus, and the world.�
We do not have parallel worries about anyone's access to beliefs about medium
sized mammals. The presence of the animals, normal light, and sensory capabilities
is enough to justify access to beliefs about those objects.
[9] � The plausible access requirement poses a challenge analogous
to galaxy clusters whenever we attribute a theory-laden concept. To credit
the interpreted community with that concept is to credit them with a philosophical
theory in which it plays a sufficiently similar role.
Since Sellars (1956), we have learned to include items such as 'sense data',
'experience', 'truth', 'belief', 'reason', and perhaps 'morality', 'right',
'duty', 'justice', and even 'God' and 'spirit' as theoretical terms in philosophy.
We can take Chinese philosophers as advocating or opposing doctrines about these
theoretical objects only if we provide a plausible argument that they had
a theory similar enough to underwrite the identification of these with our theoretical
objects.� We can take 天 tiannature:sky� as
'God' or 'Heaven' only if we can plausibly explain how ancient Chinese thinkers
would have come to a theology similar enough to ours to underwrite the identification.
[10] Otherwise, we need some plausible alternative account of how
ancient Chinese thinkers had epistemic access to these theoretical objects.�
Interpretive coherence also applies holistically to a linguistic community.
We interpret the community's linguistic practices as a whole in
ways that make coherent sense of their discourse (including the disagreements).
We theorize about the norms enshrined in the community's linguistic practices.
The norms govern how they should draw inferences from grammatical contexts using
those terms. [11] �
We then interpret any particular sentence, chapter, or book the way (according
to our theory) a representative member of that community should (as entailed
by their norms). We combine the meanings of these terms and these
structures to yield the inferential potential of a compositional sentence,
paragraph, chapter etc. In principle, the inference from those strings should
be accessible to any competent, informed reader in that original community.
There are no external �scorekeepers� so �players� keep track of each other�s
commitments.
Preserving coherence within a community's whole discourse should commit the
interpreter to maximize truth or consistency when the community is engaged
in philosophy�having philosophical disputes. However, treating as the correct
interpretation one that simply maximizes either truth or coherence over
the extant texts produces an obvious problem. We should infer that by making
more statements by sheer volume than their opponents, one philosophical faction
can make their views semantically true or consistent in that
language. Coherence should rather take the form of making sense of the dispute,
construing the terms and structures so disputants do not "talk past"
each other. Thus, I object to the proliferation of what I call "meaning-change"
hypotheses in interpretive accounts of ancient Chinese philosophy. These hypotheses
make the disputes empty. [12]
They make the communities speak a cluster of different languages.�
Disputants seem incapable of noticing that they are not disagreeing�merely speaking
Confucian or Daoist.� Community coherence allows that two discussants
might disagree about the meaning, but that in such a case, one of them should
be wrong. Neither faction can change the meaning of a term in their language
by fiat, definition or intention.
Most linguistic communities have some degree of linguistic division of labor
where the scorekeeping of �normally linguistically competent� speakers implicitly
references the scorekeeping of experts�say for inferences involving �archaeopteryx�
or �raptor.� I hold speakers responsible for the inferential commitments that
paleontologist would draw, not for those that �normal� speakers draw.� What
inferences are licensed are independent of what individual speakers think are
licensed inferences. The norms governing inferential licenses, prohibitions
and permissions are enshrined in the community�s practices not in individual
intentions. [13] The norms may be controversial, subject to discussion
and revision; the boundaries of �communities� may be variable and multiply overlapping.
[14]
Consider our contemporary philosophical scene. We do not start with an assumption
that a philosopher cannot contradict herself. Other competent philosophers may
judge that she has done so and they may be correct in that judgment.
If, according to the norms of usage enshrined in contemporary philosophical
discourse, what she says entails something of the form "P and not-P,"
then she contradicts herself. We do not approach each book as a separate radical
translation context. We do employ a mild principle of charity
on normative (usually consequential) grounds. Our cooperative pursuit of truth
is more efficient if we do not opt for the more philosophically na�ve or silly
interpretations when reporting and commenting on someone's argument. We rationally
prefer to resolve ambiguity in favorable ways, not because our theory of
meaning biases interpretation toward coherent treatment of individuals, but
because the shared pursuit of truth goes forward more efficiently if we do so.
However, the same goal (shared pursuit of knowledge) enjoins us to recognize,
attribute and announce error where the norms of interpretation, thus constrained,
clearly entail that something is incoherent.
Note the ironic situation of critics who appeal to a writer coherence principle
and reject my interpretation of arguments in the Zhuangzi as skeptical
and relativistic. If they accept the interpretive principle, should they
not read my work in a way that makes it coherent?
[15] Clearly, they need not. Now suppose that I announce (See note
3 above ) that I do not believe
what they say I do. Their correct defense is that whatever I actually believe,
the implications of what I said or wrote are as they alleged them to
be. [16] If my critics are right about
the meanings of 'skepticism' and 'relativism', then, while they may still be
wrong about my beliefs, they are right about the incoherence of my claims.
Should they not then apply the same principle to the interpretation of the Zhuangzi?
�
Nothing in the concept of 'interpretation' makes Chinese philosophers subject
to such radically different norms of assessment. Clearly, a representative reader
from the ancient Chinese philosophical community could correctly take
Zhuangzi or Mencius to have contradicted himself. Given the linguistic norms
enshrined in Warring States practice, a sentence may validly commit Mencius
to something of the form "P and not-P" whether or not he ever entertained
the thought. I argue that Zhuangzi drew such an inference about Mencius.
[17] Judging a writer to be committed to something incoherent is not a
sign of failing to understand his writing. Such judgments are not claims about
an author�s beliefs and desires.
This means that we can shift our interpretive focus from author to audience.�
What does the expression of this passage commit the writer to according to the
norms of linguistic use of some philosophical community? We are asking, "What
role do these passages play in the philosophical disagreements, given these
concepts and background arguments?" Our task is not to construct a
theory of the mental states of a sage named Zhuangzi [18] but to interpret the sentences,
arguments and theories written in the text using the community's shared language.
We will want to know what a competent ancient Chinese philosopher
reading the passage would correctly take the passage to mean, i.e., to
what would it commit one who accepted it.� The writer himself may or may not
accept or appreciate those commitments.
Communities, in the broad sense, can be at cross-purposes. Religious and philosophical
discourse may diverge and the communities effectively cease to communicate for
an extended period. Even philosophical communities may splinter and develop
in relative discourse isolation, e.g. analytic and "Continental" philosophy.
That philosophers should be particularly careful about norms of inference
does not give philosophical communities pride of place where norms of discourse
evaluation differ.
We should still reject the familiar claim that norms of discourse allow Chinese
�logical errors� as long as we have evidence of careful contemporaneous Chinese
thinkers who reliably conform to �valid� norms in reasoning. Even if a reasoning
pattern is nearly universal, evidence that a single philosophical group
recognized and diagnosed its error is enough to bar interpretive claims that
the error is �correct in Chinese� inference practices. It can be true
that some school trained nearly everyone in the community to be indifferent
to these norms, but the sheer weight of such indifference would not change
the norms.
That a community of careful, rigorous philosophy was thriving at the time of
the text is enough to warrant calling a philosophical reading 'authentic'. Ancient
Chinese literary, religious, historical and philosophically inclined
communities may all have read Daoists texts differently. The historical possibility
of other readings does not require a special justification from a philosophical
reading.� I read these passages in the Zhuangzi as philosophical, in
particular as informed by extensive contact with the school of names and ancient
Chinese semantic theory. [19]
Regardless of authorship, we should formulate for ourselves an account
of what a representative competent, thoughtful Ancient Chinese philosopher
(a contemporary with sound training) should take to be the implied commitments
of a passage or argument. We would be judging as a contemporaneous (not
contemporary) philosopher would.� In effect, philosophical interpretation
is joining those philosophers in philosophizing.
[20]
The community I focus on here is the one engaged in philosophical discourse
during the Warring States period. Hence, Graham's reconstruction of the Mohist
Dialectical works is important (along with his claim that the Zhuangzi shows
signs of familiarity with these kinds of issues).� Graham thus locates a
relevant community of philosophically sophisticated inquiry. Given his friendship
with Hui Shi, the link between a Zhuangzi persona and the community of linguistic
theory is historically firmer than the fond and familiar religious Laozi‑as‑teacher
tradition.
At the same time, we cannot rule out someone taking their representative reader
of these Zhuangzi passages from some other contemporaneous audience.
That is, we might construct the contemporaneous Huang-Lao reading or a contemporaneous
authoritarian Confucian reading of the text. There may be reasons for interest
in both--as there may be interest in the Han, Tang, Song, Japanese and other
readings. We need not speculate about how good a case one could put for treating
these other audiences as privileged for purposes of interpreting this text.�
In principle, we may equally judge two or more to be historically authentic.�
We need no further justification, however, for choosing the philosophical
one--the reading guided by the careful attention to norms of inference recognized
by the linguistic wing of the China's ancient philosophical community.�
Note that the combination of the philosophical community perspective and the
access requirement allows us to interpret these passages as a philosopher would.
It does not invite us to read them as either an ancient, enlightenment or modern
Western philosopher would.
[21] We can derive conclusions as a good philosopher would--i.e.
using sound inference, imagination, insight, etc as long as we abide by the
hypothesized norms behind ancient Chinese concepts, arguments and theories.�
If interpreters a) use crudely Western formulations of skepticism or relativism
(e.g., in terms of 'belief' or 'truth') or b) apply it to enlightenment or Greek
rationalist theories of mind, reason, meaning, ideas and so forth then c) conclude
that Zhuangzi contradicts himself in giving relativist skeptical arguments,
their reasoning would give us no reason to dismiss the skeptical-relativistic
passages. Any inference that the passages are incoherent must follow in ancient
Chinese terms, and it should be a sound inference, not an impressionistic
characterization. [22] Finally,
even when correct, the conclusion may only be that the passage is incoherent
with some other passages, not that the interpretation is wrong.
I will summarize here some philosophically important differences in formulation
and focus that distinguishes ancient Chinese schools of linguistic thought from
those most familiar in the Western tradition. These differences are relevant
to the proper formulation of Chinese skepticism, relativism and monism. My approach
below on will be mainly analytical, not textual
[23] . Readers interested in a more detailed account that stays closer to
the text can consult my (1992). Here, I will concentrate on making theoretical
distinctions to pinpoint the philosophical position I take these texts
to express. With this warning, however, I will refrain from prefixing "according
to the present interpretive hypothesis" repeatedly through the account.
Readers please note that this analysis is controversial. I do not offer the
following as observation reports, but as elements of my interpretive theory.
First, I adapt A. C. Graham's metaphor for the global character of philosophical
discourse in Classical China, i.e., I understand them as "disputes about
dao." I treat Dao as an essentially normative concept�a way.
Ways are the subject matter of practical thought as facts are the subject matter
of descriptive thought. (This is my way of reformulating the commonplace contrast
between the metaphysical focus of traditional Western thought and the practical
focus of Chinese thought.)
The familiar translation of dao as 'way' is satisfactory, though I sometimes
use 'guide' to emphasize the "normative" essence of dao-analysis.
One advantage of 'way' in the present context, however, is the rhetorical affinity
of "way of life" with important Western notions, e.g., Wittgenstein's
"form of life" and Rawls' "comprehensive view" (1993) as
well as his earlier "conception of a good life" (1971).�� These all
share important features with the Chinese conception of dao. They are
wholesale guiding structures that include ways of describing and
categorizing things for the purpose of action. The norms of meaning are
included along with those of ethics. Making certain distinctions, having certain
epistemic norms and rules of justification and so forth are components of a
dao in the sense that they are part of a comprehensive view or a "form
of life."
I divide the concept of dao into 'discourse' dao and 'performance'
dao. The former is paradigmatically verbal and written instructions.�
It embraces, however, whatever can guide us�whatever could give us knowledge
of �how to� or �what to� do.� A "performance dao" is an interpretation
into action�a practical interpretation.� It should be what a discourse
way intends or points to.� My usage here borrows from a music model. [24] The score is the discourse dao and a performance is
a "practical" interpretation.
The test of being a discourse dao is its being subject to normative
practical interpretation. Norm-guided, practical interpretation takes
the form of an execution or performance. The test of a performance dao,
then, is that it is subject to evaluation, i.e., as a right or wrong interpretation.�
One can attempt to follow a dao and get it wrong.
Many daos have both aspects. Discourse daos range from explicit
instructions and algorithms to gestures, examples, paths, maps and descriptions
of historical exemplars. Expressing, exhibiting, and gesturing are themselves
performances--subject to evaluation.� However, they are also modes of discourse--subject
to practical interpretation. Similarly, an example or model may be both performance
and discourse. To follow the example, we have to extrapolate it to our situation
and correctly identify the relevant similarities. We can go wrong following
an example as surely as we can following an instruction book.
A path can count as discourse dao (something we may "wander off"
or "stay on") or as performance dao (a "trace" of
actual past "walkings"). A road is a dao, but we should not
think of it as just a physical object like the grass, lakes, and trees
surrounding it. A road guides is, i.e. it counts as a road (way) when regarded
as something we should stay on�though we can wander off. [25]
My distinction between discourse and performance is interpretive--not a distinction
made explicitly in Chinese texts. Examples of dual-aspect dao are common
in the texts and even the best analyses blur correct interpretation and correct
choice of discourse dao [26]
"Disputing the dao" neatly captures how easy it is to
slide between the two. What is interesting is that ancient Chinese thinkers
formulated and focused on the interpretation question first and the model
of interpretation provides the dominant form for discussing what discourse dao
to choose. Choice of a dao is a performance interpretation of a "higher
order" guiding dao�one for deciding which dao to follow here.
Confucius Analects 13:3 states the interpretive problem in the form
of a doctrine of rectifying names. If names are not rectified,
. . . language . . . social affairs . . . ritual and music . . . regulation
and punishment . . . [all go wrong and] people will not know how to move hand
or foot. Mohists first raised the selection problem. The traditional
禮 liritual might be the wrong guide. Mohists proposed
utility (the benefit-harm distinction) as the guiding standard and used it to
solve both the interpretation and selection problems.
Paradigm discourse daos consist of words. To follow a dao requires
that we correctly assign the words used in it to things in the context of action.
This rests on the ability to 辯 biandistinguish and
all distinguishing can be viewed as using shi-feithis (right)-not
this (wrong) 是 非 of objects following the norms implicit
in the word�the dao of the word or the way the word is used in
the relevant community. The Mohists speak of the dao of particular distinction
pairs such as you-wu (being-nonbeing).� Thus, selecting a discourse dao
is applying shi-feithis-not this 是 非 to daos.
The Mohist ur-norm is the distinction between �利 害 li-haibenefit-harm.�
Mohists treat their disagreement with Confucians as showing the latter to be
confused about how to distinguish between義 'moral' and不義
'immoral'. [27] This way of formulating disputes
about dao made philosophy of language immediately relevant to ancient
accounts of moral disputes. The disputes are about distinctions and Mohists
called such disputes辯 biandistinction disputes. The
normative notion of a dao comprehends aspects of the Western concept
of 'meaning.' A normative dao determines the right application
and use of a guiding term�the right way to 辯 biandistinguish
using that term and its opposite.
仁 Renhumanity� might be viewed as a Confucian answer
to practical interpretation questions. The Mohists, however, used it as common
currency to challenge the Confucian conventional dao.� They asked "
. . . can we call this 仁 renhumanity and 義 yimorality?"�
Thus, 仁 renhumanity� works as a kind of dao
of daos, i.e. a dao or way of formulating and settling disputes
about dao. However, Mozi interpreted 仁 renhumanity
as universal concern and Confucius as (a notoriously undefined) something
else. A standard for interpreting can itself be subject of interpretive
dispute.
With this background, we can preview Zhuangzi's skeptical position. Choosing
and interpreting a dao are themselves performances. They presuppose some
norm, standard, distinction or dao. The Zhuangzi raises the obvious
question: What is the correct standard (dao) to use in choosing and interpreting
a dao and what is the correct dao of practical interpretation
of that standard? This initiates the relativistic regress that informs Daoist
skepticism.
Confucians and Mohists viewed the role of government as that of ensuring broad
compliance with a shared conception of the moral life--unifying the dao
of the social world. For Confucius, the ruler was like the father in inculcating
and reinforcing a conception of morality by example. Notoriously, Confucius'
wing rejected the rule of law and institutions. Good government essentially
consisted of putting a virtuous person in the father-ruler role. The Mohists
rejected the Confucian conception of morality and appealing to its traditional
status as a standard. A Mohist discourse dao would have more emphasis
on language. However, the Mohist conception of the moral education role
of government was largely congruent with that of the Confucians.
The Mohist did offer a more complex account of that role. They started with
the observation that people have different conceptions of morality (義
yimorality).� A warlike "state of nature" results
from people�s sincere, moralistic attempts to promote their different
conceptions of "the good." [28] The resulting disorder and
the inefficiency convinces everyone of the wisdom of "selecting" as
"governing [29] elder" one whom we all
regard as wise. His task is to harmonize society's 義 yimorality
.�
It is tempting to treat Mohism, qua utilitarianism, as initiating a Daoist
trend toward neutrality among conceptions of the good. It does explicitly advocate
non-partiality or universality concerning Confucian family ties, locality, etc. [30] Further, the Mozi bases its account
of utility on objective benefit and harm, not on private or subjective
pleasure or desire satisfaction. This suggests that valuing benefit over harm
is something universal and natural and does not depend on, e.g., location or
time. Still, Mohist political structure has the purpose of selecting and imposing
a single conception of shi-feithis-not this 是 非
on the polity. [31]
The political mechanism for harmonizing 義 yimorality
does start with everyone "reporting" their evaluative judgments to
their superior but it then gives the superior the performative authority
to declare which shi-feithis-not this 是 非 reports
all should accept.� After the ruler settles on the shi-feithis-not
this 是 非, the Mohist conception of government resembles
that of the Confucians more than it does that of a rule of law.� The goal is
a leader-guided acceptance of a single social dao�the Mohist difference
is in the content of that dao. Theirs would be a universal utilitarian
one where Confucians advocated a traditionalist, �partial-love� dao.
It has little relation to what Rawls would characterize as institutional structure
of ongoing neutrality among comprehensive views (daos).
The quasi-historical account of philosophy in the "Tianxia" chapter
of the Zhuangzi [32]
suggests a similar analysis. [33] � Disorder follows on the loss of a common
traditional ethical conception. This introduces the treatment of Mohism, the
first named school discussed. This internal Zhuangzi account identifies
other stages on the way to the Zhuangzi. It explicitly identifies the
others as endorsing impartiality or lack of doctrinal bias in some way. Let
us call them 1) the few-real-desires-group 2) the can't-miss-dao group
and 3) the reversibility group.
The few-real-desires-group treats most of our desires as the product of our
accepting a certain conception of the good life. Particularly, they think of
insults and shame as harms only for those who accept an optional, evaluative
point of view.� We could choose not to take that point of view that values status
or social honor.
The can't-miss-dao group
[34] , in effect, undermines the appeal to naturalness (or 天 tiannature:sky)
in selecting one way of life over another. If following the natural dao
is the goal, you do not need to work at it�you simply will. There is
no such thing as getting nature wrong.� All "live options"
for us now are equally natural�any we choose will amount to following
the Great dao. A negative way of putting the point is: 天 tiannature:sky�
gives us no basis for selecting among rival ways of life.
The reversibility group suggests that we can take any existing guidance scheme
of concepts and get an equally compelling dao by reversing all its values.
Thus, Laozi values passivity, submission, the lower position, declining, the
moist, and other female values over their Confucian-Mohist counterparts. The
distinctions and names that constitute our ways of life are not attached in
any constant way to correct guidance. This exercise, presumably,
should undermine our attachment to any particular dao.
Zhuangzi's relativistic skepticism emerges in the context of this broad social-political
movement toward impartiality and it implicitly supports that trend. The Zhuangzi's
skepticism lends support to ancient Chinese political advocacy of neutrality
among conceptions of the good life.
Before elaborating on this political point, let us look at a major contrast
in the structure we have been elaborating for disputing dao. When Chinese
thinkers elaborate on normative dao, they focus on words, which mark
distinctions. Western discussions of morality center on the role of sentences--particularly
the universal normative sentence called rules, laws, principles or maxims.
Sentential concepts pervade other aspects of Western thought. Philosophers
give reasons to construe thoughts, beliefs, propositions, judgments and even
desires as sentential (propositional) in form. Only such "sentential"
items, we learn, can be true or false. Inference, reason, and logic proceed
by moving from sentence (premise) to sentence (conclusion). Valid thinking is
thinking that preserves sentential-truth.
Western moral theory comes to focus on finding some universal "ought"
sentence�the first premise in moral reasoning. Historical Western figures speak
of moral laws, maxims, rules or principles�all of which they typically analyze
as sententials. They understand normative correctness mainly in terms of sound
normative inference. A central puzzle of Western ethical theory is what is the
"axiom" or "first premise" of moral deduction.�
Ancient Chinese thinkers, while correctly noticing the irreducibly normative
and integrated character of language, reference, knowledge, and ways of life,
did not develop this insight using sentential concepts nor did they have any
clear notion of sentential inference. They did not theorize about the norms
of sentential inference. [35] The Chinese conception of zhiknow
was, thus, non-propositional. Years ago, I analyzed it as know-how, but have
come to prefer the conception of know-to as the key to understanding
Chinese talk about zhiknow.� (An example is the rare idiomatic
use in English when we describe someone as 'knowing to come in out of the rain')
Know-how presupposes a goal and the conception of a 道 daoguide
includes both the goal and how to reach it. Knowing is knowing a dao;
to know is to have a comprehensive answer as to what to do. [36]
Chinese discourse about 心xinheart-mind uses a belief
context (S 以 yiwith T 為 weideem:do
P1) that invites term rather than sentential analysis.� The seemed
not to construe such states of mind as a relation of a 心xinheart-mind
and a sentential (a proposition, fact, state of affairs etc.).� Where Western
accounts would have a person as believing that S is P, ancient Chinese wrote
of a person as tending to treat S as P or to (say) "P" of S.
[37] � It is closer to Western accounts of de re belief. They linked
this pragmatic belief context to their theory of dao, shi-feithis-not
this是 非and 辯 biandistinction. To
為 weideem:do an object is to assign some term in a
discourse dao to it. This is the core of practical interpretation�a case
of rectifying a name. What corresponds to Western propositional beliefs are
dispositions to act toward (to treat) a thing in a certain way.
Chinese "knowing" relates to de re believing in a consistent way�zhiknow
is a success verb. It is wei-ing something correctly.
[38] It amounts to knowing to (say) P in the presence of S or knowing to
treat S as P. It underlies the evaluative judgment that our practical interpretation
is correct. Clearly, these sentential-term contrasts in talk about belief and
knowledge will give a distinctive character to Chinese monism, skepticism and
relativism.�
I shall treat monism as a metaphysical posture
[39] , skepticism as an epistemological one [40] and relativism as a posture
about standards of shi-feithis-not this 是 非
and 辯 biandistinction dispute.� We use the standards
to guide how we characterize situations or things as shi-feithis-not
this 是 非.
The context I have outlined signals that skeptical and relativist attitudes
should apply mainly to normative contexts. However, the norm analysis implicitly
presupposes a real context (realities to which we assign terms from our
daos).� I think we can appropriately describe the Daoist view as metaphysically
realist. Our conceptions of that real world may be relative to our comprehensive
views or ways of life, but the argument proceeds against a background assumption
of a reality independent of our rival conceptions. I also think we can call
the Daoist view monism�in one sense.
The dominant Western sense of 'monism' is a denial of dualisms. Robert Brandom
(1994) makes a helpful distinction between distinctions and dualisms.
A distinction becomes a dualism when accounts of it entail that one cannot explain
the relation of the two elements in terms of something common. Explaining the
interaction between the two realms typically becomes a philosophical puzzle.
Classical mind-body metaphysics is such a dualism; transcendent supernaturalism,
Plato's theory of forms, Kantian noumena-phenomena, and the like are other familiar
examples. Common-sense distinctions, however, such as male-female, old-young,
living/non-living etc. are distinctions, not dualisms.�
Notoriously, Chinese metaphysics lacks much evidence of the Indo-European mind-body
dualism and (somewhat more controversially) has little or no transcendent supernaturalism. [41] If these anti-dualist characterizations
are correct, then we can describe Chinese metaphysics as 'monist' while accepting
that they are committed to many ordinary distinctions. I think Daoists
not only accept this conception, as naturalists, they rely more strongly on
it than most other ancient schools.
Positively, a naturalistic monism envisions a continuity of nature. Like the
notorious butterfly that, by flapping its wings in Beijing, causes a blizzard
in New York [42] , our actions, causally ripple throughout
the universe. This Chinese view of the continuity of the human social world
and nature is a characteristic of Daoist reasoning that we can take as background
in reading these Zhuangzi passages and of Daoist references to "oneness"
and "unity". Their view has much of the flavor of modern physicalist
monism�e.g., when he describes his wife's death as merely a "transformation"
of the same sort that gave her birth (Ch. 18). Of course, it is not materialist
or physicalist in the sense of denying a mind-body dualism.� It is naturalistic
monism in virtue of neither presenting nor presupposing such a dualism.
Parmenidean monism, by contrast, is the denial not merely of dualisms but of
distinctions. It commits one to a peculiarly strong version of one-ness, i.e.,
not merely of some underlying natural continuity. Parmenidean monism denies
all qualitative and quantitative difference. Besides Parmenides, Neo-Platonism,
Spinoza, and some idealist views of "the absolute" may approach
this kind of Monism about absolute reality. It seems to find expression in Indian
Upanishadic and Buddhist metaphysics as well. It tends to be associated with
mystical epistemic doctrines and semantics since, typically, it is hard to prove
or to state without paradox. The traditional religious view of the Zhuangzi
(and Daoism generally) reads references to unity, oneness, etc. as Parmenidean
rather than naturalistic monism and links it to the mysticism of Indo-European
traditions.
I argue that classical China offers some candidates for rough [43] counterparts of this stronger
kind of Monism. Something like this may be the conclusion of Zhuangzi's
philosophical companion, Hui Shi. [44] The metaphysics of what I called the "can't-miss-dao"
group also suggests an intermediate kind of monism. Its core is continuity-of-nature
monism, but from that premise Shen Dao seems to derive a prohibition on our
making any distinction between shi-feithis-not this
是 非.�
I have argued that a philosophical reader could reasonably take passages in
the Zhuangzi to reject both views. Graham drew our attention to the fact
that Zhuangzi seems to formulate and then reject Hui Shi's position (an attempt
to derive 'all is one' from observations about concept relativism).
"Nothing in the world is bigger than the tip of an autumn
hair, and Mount T'ai is small; no one lives longer than a doomed child, and
P'eng-tsu died young; heaven and earth were born together with me, and the myriad
things and I are one.
Now that we are one, can I still say something? Already having
called us one, did in succeed in not saying something? One and the saying make
two; two and one make three. Proceeding from here even an expert calculator
cannot get to the end of it, much less a plain man." (Chapter 2 Graham
1981:56)
Zhuangzi's line here relates closely to arguments we find in the Mohist dialectical
chapters. They pointed out that eschewing distinctions is unacceptable. "Denying
denial is perverse." (Canon B79)� The Mohists also rebutted, on coherence
grounds, a closely related anti-language view."� "To take language
as exhaustively perverse is perverse." (Canon B71, see Graham 1978:445-6)
Their acceptance of the then common analysis of language as consisting in distinctions
unites these two paradoxes. Rejecting all distinctions is tantamount to rejecting
language and vice-versa. Hui Shi, from the fragments available, tended to conclude
from the relativity of distinctions to perspective that there were no distinctions
in reality. Someone familiar with linguistic work would have good grounds for
rejecting this inference. Zhuangzi's point here is that rejecting distinctions
is implicit in the claim that "all is one." We cannot make it without
making a distinction. "Having said, "all is one" have we managed
to say anything?"� Zhuangzi saw that we cannot soundly draw an absolute
conclusion about reality from relativist premises about words, distinctions
and reference.
The Zhuangzi writer(s) show no signs of being relativist or pluralist
about the world (i.e., committed to many metaphysically real worlds).
The text, however, certainly expresses a descriptive norm-pluralism (many
norms systems exist, including higher level norms for choosing/interpreting
lower-level norms).� Moreover, it is skeptical (agnostic) about
normative realism. He is unsure that one and only one of the existing norm systems
is correct.
Skepticism about our ability to choose from the many available guiding systems
and skepticism about our ways of distinguishing things are two manifestations
of skepticism about daos. We get access to the reality that is relevant
to acting through our daos or "comprehensive views." These
"forms of life" include our norms of discrimination, of distinction,
and of classification into "things" or "types" for purposes
of action.
My conclusion is that the Zhuangzi shares with many writers of the period
an implicitly naturalistic-monist conception of the world. However, it rejects
the invitation to treat this monism as Parmenidean�as warranting a blanket denial
of distinctions. However, speculation about what is ultimately real is not the
central philosophical project of the period. [45] The Zhuangzi aims its skeptical attitude
at conceptions of the world that inform our various, rival concepts of
what counts as the good life--dao.
Skepticism is a complex epistemological stance. Following Goldman (1986), we
can distinguish among many varieties of skepticism by focusing on its different
themes, its scope and its strength.
[47] We can use these distinctions with appropriate modifications
in the different conceptual context of Chinese thought. To do so, we should
avoid formulating them in terms of sententials or sententially linked concepts
such as truth, belief, or inference. The appropriate counterparts would be distinctions
or shi-feithis-not this 是 非 assignments (approximating
judgments), dispositions to treat as shi-feithis-not this
是 非 (approximating thoughts) and appeal to standards (a 法
fastandardor a 道 daoguide) for treating
as shi-feithis-not this 是 非 (approximating inference).�
These concepts underlie ancient accounts of knowing-to, knowing how-to, and
contact-knowing (acquaintance).
Gaptooth asked Wang Ni.� 'Do you know what all things treat as是
shithis:right?'� 'How could I know that?'� 'Do you know what
it is you do not know?'� 'How could I know that'?� 'So in that case, does no
one know anything?'� ' How could I know that? Still, let me try to state it
- "How do I know that what I call knowing is not non-knowing? How do I
know that what I call non-knowing is not knowing?"� HY 6/2/64-66.
Several recent writers deny that Zhuangzi's is direct skepticism about our
epistemic achievements�whether we have knowledge. They draw parallels to ancient
Greek Pyrrhonian skepticism and construe Zhuangzi's theme as non-epistemic�as
a posture aiming at some envisioned good. They aver that Zhuangzi's apparent
skepticism is not really a negative thesis about our epistemic achievements
but a recommendation about an attitude we ought to adopt (suspension
of judgment) to get peace of mind. They justify this reinterpretation as a way
to avoid an inconsistency in skepticism�the skeptic cannot know that he does
not know. [48] If one claimed
to know that no one knew, there would be a problem, but it can hardly
be a problem with skeptical doubt as a philosophical attitude. The problem arises
if the skeptic asserts the doubt in the form of a skeptical conclusion "no
one knows anything" and acknowledges the norm of asserting that
acknowledges the familiar challenge "how do you know that" as one
that binds him to withdraw the assertion if he cannot vindicate that he does
know it.� The content of the assertion itself is fully consistent.
The doubt illustrated in the Gaptooth discussion entails no inconsistency and,
arguably, is carefully drawn to avoid it. Its root is worry that the standards
for using terms like "know" and "don't know" could be other
than they are. The anti-skeptical interpreters do not soundly derive the incoherent
conclusions from things in the Zhuangzi and, even if they had, their
derivation would not have been accessible to a Zhuangzi (i.e. he would not have
formulated it in terms of 'truth', 'belief' or 'meaning'). The "irony"
of their therapeutic solutions to the bogus problem is that they are plainly
incoherent since the content of the judgment is "we should not make
any judgment."� Further, its incoherence is precisely the one identified
and criticized by the ancient Mohists and the Zhuangzi passage (D.1
above ). Both would easily spot the "perversity" in recommending
that we not make judgments.
They choose the "therapeutic" strategy to rescue the traditional
view of Zhuangzi as a religious or spiritual guide from the threat to that
view posed by the skeptical passages. I certainly accept the value of examining
the broader significance of the skepticism in the Zhuangzi, but
I doubt this could be it.� First, I do not see why the possibility of a wider
theme and significance for skeptical lines of reasoning should rule out
that the text also expresses skepticism in the familiar sense of straightforward
doubt of our epistemic achievements. It seems to me obvious that it does.
[49] Second, I conclude that a representative philosophical reader/writer
should find this significance in the political implications, rather than some
recipe for spiritual edification. [50]
a) Doubts about knowing and the basis of
knowing.
While accepting the value of giving the wider implications of skepticism, I
will not call those implications 'skepticism'. I restrict that term,
as contemporary philosophical usage does, to philosophical doubts about knowing
or justifying, bearing in mind, however, that in the Chinese contexts,
the 'knowing' is practical, not propositional and 'justifying' is not sentential
inference but appeal to some standard for making a distinction. The doubt is
about whether we do know to make the distinctions that underlie our action choices.
As I noted above, we can draw broad parallels between Chinese
and Western conceptual structures for epistemic discussion. The rough counterpart
of 'belief' would be de re wei-ing (i.e., deeming-for-action)
attitudes. That is to say, skeptical doubt centers on the normative assumption
that we have wei-ed correctly when we distinguish between things
particularly as they are relevant to our action.
Chinese thinkers of the period did not distinguish questions about causation
and warrant of beliefs. Most explicitly, the Mohists recognize that we appeal
to standards for applying guiding distinctions in the course of dao-ing�giving
guidance. The Zhuangzi often presents such considerations in terms of
an ambiguous dependence.
[51] One shi-feithis-not this是 非depends
on a prior shi-feithis-not this是 非.� The view
I defend is that the Zhuangzi passages express skepticism in the context
of their awareness that our judgments always have this dependence (causal or
rational) on prior shi-feithis-not this是 非 judgments.
This leads to the rough counterpart of a skeptical theme focusing on relativity
of justification.
Not yet to have it grown in the heart-mind and yet to have shi-feithis-not
this是 非is like going to Yue today and arriving yesterday.
(Ch. 2) HY 4/2/22
The Zhuangzi passages play on the view that people use many norms or
standards of what would be correct wei-ing. The clearest case is Mozi's
famous three-standards: [52] (1) conformity to traditional shi-feithis-not
this是 非 assignments, (2) measurable, empirical standards
for word use, and (3) moral and utilitarian considerations. The plurality means
possible conflict and entails that we will draw on some higher standard to tell
us which to use in cases of conflict.
[53]
We do not know which wei-ing is correct unless we know which standard
to use. However, knowing that is another 'knowing-to'. Claims to know, thus,
face a regress. The requirement that we know-to apply these rather than
those higher norms and standards in interpreting or selecting the lower
ones suggests that we presuppose a dao when we interpret (or select)
a dao. The regress of implicit daos on which our judgments depend
lies behind the Zhuangzi expression of skepticism. We cannot escape
dao. Humans live in dao as fish live in water. HY 18/6/72-3
The scope of a skeptical attitude refers to the areas of knowledge it calls
into question. Thus, one may be a religious skeptic or a skeptic about other
minds, sense data, physical objects, or ethics.
[54] � One's skepticism may be narrow (e.g. my skepticism about current
Ancient Chinese textual theory or our reconstructions of "the sounds of
classical Chinese") or broad (e.g. skepticism of the external world). Most
recognizable skepticism has some implicitly limited scope that it contrasts
with some paradigm of what we can know.
Most accounts agree that the Zhuangzi skeptical passages suggest a rather
broad scope. While the skepticism resembles ethical skepticism in revolving
around the regress of norms, it implicitly embraces all linguistic classification�since
these are subject to norms. A dao, a conception of a good life, includes
in itself the good or right ways of classifying and identifying
things. In China, the doubts focus on linguistic classification more than on
sense experience, other minds, and physical or theoretical objects. The scope
of such doubt however affects the whole scheme that underlies our "knowing
what to do." The object of doubt is the comprehensive, guiding view that
constitutes our "form of life."�
Stories of surprises, gestalt shifts and dreams all play a skeptical role. [55] These are familiar themes in the Zhuangzi.� Here are
some examples:
[Zhuang Zhou pursued a strange magpie into a preserve.] He noticed
a cicada finding such lovely shade it forgot itself. A mantis poised itself
to strike, so taken with the vision of opportunity it forgot its own situation.
The strange magpie on seeing its own gain forgot an authentic urge.� Zhuang
zhou said "Eee! Things are inherently connected and kinds are interdependent."�
As he threw down his bow to leave, a game warden caught up and accosted him.
Ch. 20 HY 6/20/61-4
Have only you not heard how in fleeing the invasion of Jia,
Lin Hui discarded a priceless treasure to carry his infant child to safety.
Some say "is it for value? However, the child's value was lesser; was it
to facilitate fleeing: but the child was more trouble.� Why then abandon the
treasure and take the child? Lin Hui said, "One was beneficial, the other
was natural." So beneficial things are cast aside in times of disaster
and urgency. Natural affiliations are embraced in such times. The times of embracing
and discarding are very different. Ch. 20 HY 53/20/38-41
Hui Tzu said to Chuang Tzu, I have a big tree named ailanthus
Its trunk is too gnarled and bumpy to apply a measuring line to, its branches
too bent and twisty to match up to a compass or square. You could stand it by
the road and no carpenter would look at it twice. Your words, too, are big and
useless, and so everyone alike spurns them!"
Chuang Tzu said, "�Now you have this big tree and you're
distressed because it's useless. Why don't you plant it in Not‑Even‑Anything
Village, or the field of Broad‑and‑Boundless, relax and do nothing
by its side, or lie down for a free and easy sleep under it? Axes will never
shorten its life; nothing can ever harm it. If there's no use for it, how can
it come to grief or pain?" Ch. 1 HY 3/1/43-7 [Watson]
Hui Tzu said to Chuang Tzu, "The king of Wei gave me some
seeds of a huge gourd. I planted them, and when they grew up, the fruit was
big enough to hold five piculs. I tried using it for a water container, but
it was so heavy I couldn't lift it I split it in half to make dippers, but they
were so large and unwieldy that I couldn't dip them into anything. It's not
that the gourds weren't fantastically big but I decided they were no use and
so I smashed them to pieces."
Chuang Tzu said, "You certainly are dense when it comes
to using big things! In Sung, there was a man who was skilled at making a salve
to prevent chapped hands, and generation after generation his family made a
living by bleaching silk in water. A traveler heard about the salve and offered
to buy the prescription for a hundred measures of gold. The man called everyone
to a family council. 'For generations we've been bleaching silk and we've never
made more than a few measures of gold,' he said. 'Now, if we sell our secret,
we can make a hundred measures in one morning. Let's let him have it!' The traveler
got the salve and introduced it to the king of Wu who was having trouble with
the state of Yueh. The king put the man in charge of his troops, and that winter
they fought a naval battle with the men of Yueh and gave them a bad beating.
A portion of the conquered territory was awarded to the man as a fief. The salve
had the power to prevent chapped hands in either case; but one man used it to
get a fief, while the other one never got beyond silk bleaching because they
used it in different ways. Now you had a gourd big enough to hold five piculs.
Why didn't you think of making it into a great tub so you could go floating
around the rivers and lakes, instead of worrying because it was too big and
unwieldy to dip into things! Obviously you still have a lot of underbrush in
your head!" Ch. 1 HY 2/1/35-42 [Watson]
Last night Chuang Chou dreamed he was a butterfly; spirits soaring
he was a butterfly (is it that in showing what he was he suited his own fancy?),
and did not know about Chou. When all of a sudden he awoke, he was Chou with
all his wits about him. He does not know whether he is Chou who dreams he is
a butterfly or a butterfly who dreams he is Chou. Ch. 2 HY 7/2/94-6 [Graham]
These accounts of suddenly seeing things differently remind us that the challenge
of correctly wei-ing has a "metaphysical" dimension
filtering through our background categorizations. Zhuangzi the hunter in a grove
feels confident (and smugly superior) as he stalks a bird that is also engaged
in stalking a mantis that is about to pounce on a cicada. Little does each know
he is the hunted as well as the hunter. When the "keeper" surprises
Zhuangzi and chases him from the grove, he sees his confidence and sense of
superiority as foolishness. He recognizes his likeness to the chain of prey
he had been observing. An unappreciated feature of the context made him suddenly
reclassify himself and other things differently for purposes of guiding action.
"How do I know that loving life is not a delusion?
How do I know that in hating death I am not like a man who, having left home
in his youth, has forgotten the way back?
"Lady Li was the daughter of the border guard of Ai. When
she was first taken captive and brought to the state of Chin, she wept until
her tears drenched the collar of her robe. But later, when she went to live
in the palace of the ruler, shared his couch with him, and ate the delicious
meats of his table, she wondered why she had ever wept. How do I know that the
dead do not wonder why they ever longed for life? Ch. 2 HY 6/2/78-81 [Watson]
The Zhuangzi also targets norms of judgment that seem beyond challenge.
We normally "know to do" things that keep us alive, but some ways
of life (conceptions of the good life) sometimes treat accepting death as rational.
Is this an objection to them?� The Zhuangzi asks, "How do I know
that avoiding death is not a similar mistake?"� Without knowing that I
should value life, I cannot claim to know to do any of the things
in which pragmatic survival (individual or social) is a motivating standard.
Zhuangzi's conversation with the skull illustrates by portraying even this judgment
as one that we could not motivate from the rival point of view.
When Chuang Tzu went to Ch�u, he saw an old skull, all dry and
parched. He poked it with his carriage whip and then asked, �Sir, were you greedy
for life and forgetful of reason, and so came to this? Was your state overthrown
and did you bow beneath the ax and so came to this? Did you do some evil deed
and were you ashamed to bring disgrace upon your par�ents and family, and so
came to this? Was it through the pangs of cold and hunger that you came to this?
Or did your springs and autumns pile up until they brought you to this?�
When he had finished speaking, he dragged the skull over and,
using it for a pillow, lay down to sleep.
In the middle of the night, the skull came to him in a dream and
said, �You chatter like a rhetorician and all your words betray the entanglements
of a living man. The dead know nothing of these! Would you like to hear a lecture
on the dead?�
�Indeed,� said Chuang Tzu.
The skull said, �Among the dead there are no rulers above, no
subjects below, and no chores of the four seasons. With nothing to do, our springs
and autumns are as endless as heaven and earth. A king facing south on his throne
could have no more happiness than this!�
Chuang Tzu couldn�t believe this and said, �If I got the Arbiter
of Fate to give you a body again, make you some bones and flesh, return you
to your parents and family and your old home and friends, you would want that,
wouldn�t you?�
The skull frowned severely, wrinkling up its brow. �Why would
I throw away more happiness than that of a king on a throne and take on the
troubles of a human being again?� it said. Ch. 18� HY46/18/22-9 [Watson]
Other species -based doubt expands on the theme. Clearly, the extinction of
humans would seem threatened species not to be such a bad thing.
Mao-ch'iang and Lady Li were beautiful in the eyes of men; but
when the fish saw them they plunged deep, when the birds saw them they flew
high, when the deer saw them they broke into a run. Which of these four knows
what is truly beautiful in the world? In my judgment the principles of Goodwill
and Duty, the paths of "That's it, that's not", are inextricably confused;
how could I know how to discriminate between them?'� Ch. 2 HY 6/2/69-70 [Graham]
Dream passages illustrate the theme by showing how, in dreams, we classify
others and ourselves in one way with little hesitation then on awakening, abandon
that classification instantly. We cannot convince the "dream persona"
that it is wrong.�� Am I Zhuangzi dreaming being a butterfly or a butterfly
dreaming Zhuangzi? Do we know how to treat the dream context?� Some ways
of life treat dreams as important identifications of one's religious status,
some as prophesies, some as revelations of deep structures of desire, etc. Are
we right merely to dismiss what we "knew" during the dream?
The main target of doubt in these passages is conventional wisdom, especially
our shared, conventional patterns of discrimination or distinction making. A
key claim is that any time we make a discrimination, we fail to see something
(as Zhuangzi fails to see the gamekeeper while discriminating the bird
as unwitting prey).
That the scope is broad, however, does not mean that it is total. It does not,
as we noted above, signal any doubt about the real-world context in which our
ways of life operate nor that the ways operate in the same world nor that we
have different ones and disagree about them.
Besides reminders of how we can go wrong, the stories mainly underline the
irresolvability of our disputes about different ways of life and the difficulty
of appreciating alternatives.� They remind us that our confidence in our own
comprehensive view is neither reliable nor unique to us. The text naturally
implies that we are to learn (come to know) something from these stories. This
knowing about knowing is valuable. Ignoring it would bad from many, if not
all, points of view.
Broad but not total skepticism of this type can support a normative conclusion
� as it does for modern liberalism. The conclusion would be that we ought not
to participate in social structures designed to oppress, mutilate, or kill those
who do not share our way of life. Engaging in coercive activities to impose
a single way of life on people requires a level of confidence that we have identified
the correct comprehensive vision to which we are not entitled.� The Zhuangzi
passages remind us of that we have frequently been wrong in our classifications
and action attitudes toward things.
The strength of a skeptical doubt is independent of its scope. A very broad
skepticism might still be weak and a narrow skepticism might be quite strong.
The stronger the demand the skeptic requires to justify a claim to knowledge,
the weaker the skeptical considerations have to be to support the judgment that
we do not or cannot have it.� There are various dimensions of strength.�
a) Doubt of perfect knowledge or any
knowledge?
Denying that we can be certain of something is a weak version of skepticism
because 'certainty' is a strong demand. Similarly, denying that we now know
X now weaker than modal versions, which deny any possibility of
knowing X. The Gaptooth discussion suggests that the Zhuangzi position
is weak in that it allows we might in fact know something, but do not
know that we know it. [56]
Thus, it does not commit us to the claim that knowledge is impossible.�
The passages under discussion do not use notions like 'certainty', but the
skepticism still looks weak in a vaguely similar sense. The surprise and dream
passages suggest that skepticism about how to act is comparative.
We may know a way to do a thing, but not plausibly claim to know the
way or the best way to do it. There are always possibilities we have
not yet even contemplated. We learn from our experiences of coming to realize
a better way to view and act that we typically tend to have too much confidence
that our way is the way of doing something.
Consider the story of the protective hand-salve used by its inventor for bleaching
silk, which was later adapted to a military use by an enterprising stranger.
(Ch. 1) It worked as well or better to that purpose and brought the entrepreneur
greater status and monetary rewards. The inventor did know a way to
use of the salve, but he clearly did not know the correct use. A better
use, one that he had never even thought of, was available.
The dream sequences make a similar point. We learn that one way of life is
not correct when we "awaken" to one that seems better. Each such "awakening"
is a kind of knowing--that our past confidence was misleading about our epistemic
status. We know then that we did not know before what we thought we knew. The
repeated experience of coming to know should make us cautious, modest about,
or present state of knowledge. Even when our prior ways have seemed to work
fine, they have turned out to come to seem inferior to some alternative. Typically,
we had not even imagined the alternative.
The guidance-skepticism is thus weak in that it denies mainly that we can ever
have perfect, ultimate, the highest or best knowledge.
The demand is a strong one, so the skepticism is weak. We cannot intelligently
treat or regard our way of doing things as unqualifiedly best. This is,
of course, precisely the kind of dao skepticism that justifies neutrality
among comprehensive views and encouraging the spread of different daos.
However, in making this point, the skeptic acknowledges that we can come
to realize (know) that one dao is better than another. We simply cannot
conclude that with this realization we have found the way.
Again, notice that this skepticism does not arise from any analysis of our
representations or of memory v. some reality.� It takes both memory and our
past for granted in appealing to our common past experiences of coming to
see as dubious what we had thought obvious.
One may object that the skepticism is so weak that it really has no
opponents. However, the tradition defends us from accusations of triviality.
We find many claims in Confucian
[57] and other authoritarian (Proto-legalist) writing that "sages"
are capable of transcending the ordinary limited perspectives and achieving
something like total or fully rounded knowledge. In any case, the interpretative
claim is not trivial since the dominant rival interpretation is that Zhuangzi
himself claims access to Confucian-like perfect knowledge. Traditional
interpretations take the skill stories as endorsing just such a claim. [58]
The Zhuangzi also observes that skillful performers are all limited
to their skill. Inevitably, other things they cannot do as well.� Perhaps their
focus in gaining the skill hinders them from getting some other valuable ability.
Typically, the stories note that the skillful practitioner cannot convey his
skill to his son. A musician cannot play all notes at once; a debater cannot
convince everyone etc. He sums up by noting that 成chengcompletion
always entails 虧kuidefect.
May men like this be said to be complete? Then so am I. Or may
they not be said to be complete? Then neither am I, nor is anything else. Ch.
2 [Graham] HY 5/2/46-7
The no-completion-without-defect insight reminds us that no matter how much
we perfect our skill, we will be unable to do other things. This is rooted in
the linguistic point.� Anytime we learn to make and follow a distinction, there
will be things we are unable to appreciate or respond to. To make a distinction
is to choose not to make other possible distinctions in the context.
Hence, divisions have that which they do not divide; distinctions
have that they do not distinguish. You say, "What does this mean?"
Sages embrace things, ordinary people discriminate things so they can see them
in relation to each other; so I say, those who distinguish have that they do
not see. Ch. 2 HY 5/2/57
Normally, we regard our way of life as better than the ways of others.
We might even be right about it. However, the skeptical passages warn us that
our evaluation to this effect is suspect. It may be question-begging
because others may not share our standards of evaluation. We might accidentally
be right, but we cannot conclude that we are so merely from the strength
of our conviction, nor can we merely because we appeal to higher standards.
A rival dao comes complete with its own different norms of warrant.
Is man's life really as stupid as this? Or is it that I am the
only stupid one, and there are others not so stupid? But if you go by the completed
heart and take it as your authority, who is without such an authority? Why should
it be only the man who knows how things alternate and whose heart approves its
own judgments who has such an authority? Ch.2 [Graham] HY4/2/20-2
We would be unwise to ignore that the person with the rival form of
life probably finds hers superior on functionally similar grounds. That
is, though she does not appeal to the same norms, she does appeal to
norms of warrant and they may justify and convince her in as complex and
complete a way.� She may equally cite her dao's success in the actual
world as judged by those norms. She too will have a skill, albeit not
the same as ours. The crucial skeptical realization is that we can no more easily
convince her that our way of life is better than she can us.
I referred to how dream passages illustrate the effect of conversion from one
comprehensive view to another.� When we are "within" one way of life,
we find it obviously correct.� When we have awakened to a different
way, we equally clearly realize how we were wrong before. We become
as strongly convinced of our new view
[59] That we can so easily come to see things "in a new light"
should lead us to realize how real the danger is that we may be misled merely
by the reflective elaboration of a dao we accept.
How should the philosophically alert reader then make sense of the interspersing
of these skeptical passages with talk about "perfected" people and
absolutes? What they might find striking about such passages is that they often
suggest that such perfection is unintelligible and irrelevant to us.
[60] Unintelligible, some examples suggest, even to the highest religious
sage�the Yellow emperor (HY 6/2/71-6).�
Nieh Ch'ueh said, "If you don't know what is profitable or
harmful, then does the Perfect Man likewise know nothing of such things?"
Wang Ni replied, "The Perfect Man is godlike. Though the great swamps blaze,
they cannot burn him; though the great rivers freeze, they cannot chill him;
though swift lightning splits the hills and howling gales shake the sea, they
cannot frighten him. A man like this rides the clouds and mist, straddles the
sun and moon, and wanders beyond the four seas. Even life and death have no
effect on him, much less the rules of profit and loss!
. . .
The sage leans on the sun and moon, tucks the universe under his
arm, merges himself with things, leaves the confusion and muddle as it is, and
looks on slaves as exalted. Ordinary men strain and struggle; the sage is stupid
and blockish. He takes part in ten thousand ages and achieves simplicity in
oneness. For him, all the ten thousand things are what they are, and thus they
enfold each other. Ch. 2 [Watson] HY� 6/2/71-6
Typically, this kind of text makes its point by asserting a kind of reversal.
Perfection may be the very opposite of what we now take it to be. Perfection
from one perspective may appear as stupidity from another! The perfect musician
may be one who does not play a note(?!).
[61] � The judgments and behavior of a perfect man are just irrelevant,
incomprehensible to us and of no use when we, ordinary people, think about what
to do.
Our lives are bounded and knowledge is unbounded. To use the bounded
to pursue the unbounded is dangerous�stop it and you can be deemed a knowledgeable
person. Ch.3 HY 7/3/1
We can also read passages like "A man like this rides the clouds and mist," [62] as contemplating what might be possible with
different daos. Some comprehensive way of life that is possible for
us, might give us powers over nature and our lives that we can now barely
conceive of.� That is another sense that should lead us to doubt that we now
know how to live. There almost certainly are far better possible ways to
organize our lives, whose superiority we could appreciate even using our
present norms.
(1) Arguments
Besides theme, scope and strength, we can classify dominant arguments for skepticism.
Here I will strategically focus on the two most relevant to understanding skepticism
in the Zhuangzi. One line of argument draws on the fallibility of human
cognitive faculties the other on the question of the grounds or warrant. Clearly,
my analysis is that the core argument for skepticism in the Zhuangzi is
of the latter kind. The skepticism appears to flow mainly from the dependency
analysis of knowing-to as presupposing standards and which opens up a regress
of knowing-to use certain standards and how to use them.
The most common alternative in the literature on Zhuangzi's skepticism is human
fallibility�particularly of the senses. Do these passages suggest that the ground
of the skepticism is a view of the limitations of the human mind (Say as contrasted
to the transcendent supernatural)? Aside from the implicit claim that the judgments
of a perfect being are irrelevant to our deciding what to do, there is scant
evidence in this texts or the tradition for any negative analysis of human
cognitive psychology. [63] The main limitation we face is "our lives are bounded."�
We find none of the familiar appeals to relativity or fallibility of sense perception.
The Zhuangzi does sometime makes its skeptical point in physiological
terms. It refers to a 成cheng xin as a physiological tendency that
respond to things with shi-feithis-not this 是 非. It "grows" in the heart just as the heart
grows in the body. The point there, however, simply recapitulates the regress-of-norms
argument. All shi-feithis-not this 是 非 emerging
from the heart rely on having some other shi-feithis-not this
是 非 already present there. As I have argued (Hansen 1992), the
discussion of the heart approximates (i.e., translates with appropriate conceptual
adjustments) the Humean skeptical point "you can't get an ought from an
is." The heart-mind's judgments are dependent it its having absorbed the
shi-feithis-not this 是 非 presuppositions of
a "way of life."
The Zhuangzi is skeptical of any claims to innate, self-warranting knowledge.
This point is also most famously put in physiological terms--that the 心
xinheart-mind is a product of its conditions of growth.� It
does not have innate or direct (intuitive) access to the correct answer to a
know-to question. The philosophical context presents us with numerous targets
for this skeptical argument. Graham identified the most obvious example of such
an epistemological claim--Mencian intuitionism. Mencius implied that all human
hearts are born with a naturally accurate inclination to shi-feithis-not
this 是 非. [64]
Other versions of ancient Chinese claims of access to transcendent or
perfect epistemic accuracy in shi-feithis-not this
是 非 judgments attribute the access to some form of breath-control
or self-cultivation. Scholars have recently begun to highlight accounts drawn
from the Guanzi and the Xunzi.
[65] For sake of argument , let us accept the interpretive accounts. The
issue is whether, as these scholars imply, such positions are sound rejections
of Zhuangzi's skepticism.� I argue they are not.� The Zhuangzi's "dependency"
arguments work as well against claims of perfect knowledge via innate, or cultivated,
physical or religiously transcendent intuitions. We require both a norm to justify
our reliance on the intuitive capacity and a norm to guide our use of it before
we can vouchsafe that we have used it correctly, or followed the right intuition.
I have argued that this important skeptical theme is a crucial warning to those
adopting the common interpretive posture that all Chinese thought assumes
this essentially religious "guru" posture. [66] I do not deny its existence
or its familiarity in China. However, I do deny that such self-aggrandizing
claims to some mysterious access to knowledge would impress a philosophically
competent judge. [67] Had they
understood the Zhuangzi argument, they should not have acknowledged such
claims--even if those claims were found elsewhere in the Zhuangzi.
Baldly alleging, as the religious writers of China do, that some
esoteric method enables them to make dependency-free judgments does not answer
the skeptical point made in the Zhuangzi.� It simply discredits the claimants
by confirming the non-reflective, religious character of their own thought processes.
The contemporary Chinese philosophically trained reader of such texts
should have no reason to accept their boast. The argument does not rest
on the limitations of human capacity (something that conceivably could be altered
by trances, diets, breathing, etc.), it is about an open-ended regress of warrant.
Ancient Chinese thinkers demonstrably had more than sufficient reason to
doubt that any cultivation could give transcendental epistemic
access to a perfect way to live. Until someone in that culture produced
a sound counter-argument to the position stated in these passages of the Zhuangzi,
the qualified, contemporary reader of these texts should have been skeptical.
Now what of 21st century readers [68] who allege that the implication of other passages
or texts is something like this religious or dogmatic claim? First, that interpretive
claim is itself subject to scrutiny by the same standard. I.e., should a competent
skeptical philosopher who understood the arguments from the analytic wing of
Chinese thought understand the passage to entail a religious claim? Of course,
it could. The contemporaneous philosophical reader could understand passages
he considered fatuous or na�ve. He would have no reason to conclude that the
passage--even right next to a skeptical passage--could change the meaning
of the skeptical passages. [69] They would simply conflict. The conflict
is fully intelligible because the skepticism is precisely what the philosophical
context invites. It casts doubt on any faith that there could be "sages,"
of the kind required by authoritarian political doctrines.
This strategy of reading leaves room for goals of personal or social transformation,
but not for peculiarly religious, spiritual, or transcendent
goals. In emphasizing here the social-political implications, I do not mean
to deny that any practical value can be derived from the relativistic skeptical
insights. [70] � Common-sense
implications abound.� One is tolerance, flexibility and open mindedness about
other daos and their possible value in adapting our own. This underwrites
the famous Zhuangzi willingness to listen respectfully to freaks, convicted
criminals, seemingly insane philosophers, centipedes and skulls. The practical
implication of this kind of skepticism is that we (socially or individually)
should not waste daos. [71]
The term 'relativism' has such a bad press among non-philosophers that some
avoid it in preference to terms like pluralism, perspectivism
etc.� I can confirm that the word attracts more heat than light, but am inclined
to resist the common tendency to "blame the word."� I find all three
terms helpful in bringing out different aspects of the position enunciated in
the Zhuangzi. One advantage of 'pluralism' and 'perspectivalism' is that
they more naturally draw attention away from truth to warrant or justification.
'Pluralism' emphasizes that there may be multiple warranted answers.�
'Perspectivism' is a common way to fill out the relativist formula and draws
our attention to how the broadly epistemic context� and our conceptual backgrounds
shape and warrant different answers.
The usage of 'relativism' is even less philosophically standardized than is
'skepticism' so it is even more dangerous to take it to refer to a credo
to which Zhuangzi was converted so that my characterizing Zhuangzi as
a relativist can warrant attributing some fixed set of beliefs to him based
on some commentator's definition of the term. These terms simply help us characterize
accurately the thrust (implications) of arguments, conceptions, and reflections
in the Zhuangzi.
Broadly speaking, a relativist analysis of a subject matter implies
the way to fully answer certain questions about that topic uses phrases like
"it depends on. . . ."� Relativist analyses loosely contrast with
absolutist ones, which detach full answers from any context. Consider
the most familiar example of relativism.� To answer "how fast are we traveling?"
with "Thirty miles an hour" is incomplete. It should be "thirty
miles an hour relative to the surface of the earth." It could also be "about
a thousand miles an hour relative to the pivot of the earth's rotation"
or "around 65000 miles per hours per hour relative to the sun."� In
other words, the correct answer begins with "it depends." The
pre-Einstein "absolute" analysis, by contrast, presupposed a matrix
of absolute time and space so that exactly one, unqualified answer to that question
is fully correct.
Some writers have used 'relativism' to contrast with 'realism'.� The issue
turns on complicated explications of the Western concepts of 'truth' or 'meaning'.
I have argued [72] that such explications are remote from ancient Chinese philosophical
concerns, which we better understand as dealing with pragmatic counterparts
such as "warranted assertability" and "appropriate use."
Most forms of relativism presuppose a kind of realism. We take Einstein to have
discovered the correct way to describe motion and take the classical
notion of absolute space-time to be wrong. I have argued that relativism in
the Zhuangzi takes for granted the existence of a natural reality that is independent
of us.
Relativism does not imply that all views are warranted, justified or rational. [73] If we fill the above ellipsis with something
like "some perspective," relativism may allow that for any
view, there is a perspective from which such a view is rational. However, there
need be no perspective that warrants all views and, possibly, some views are
unwarranted from any perspective (e.g. logical contradictions and counter-intuitives).�
As argued above, the Zhuangzi uses relativism to support skepticism
by illustrating how our confidence in our knowing the way to act is dependent
of factors we have not actively considered or leaving out possibilities that
have not occurred to us.� He stimulates our awareness that people with rival
perspectives acquire equal confidence from their different background
standards. Our confidence in the "obviousness" of our view is not
a reliable guide to knowledge. The relativism thus fuels the skepticism. [74]
Distinctions like those we used to pinpoint the skepticism can help us locate
what is distinctive about the Zhuangzi's relativist arguments. The caveats
about the changed philosophical context all apply here as well.
Relativism, too, may have various themes.� The above contrast between truth
and warrant is a component of theme as is the focus on perspective. Most important,
we obviously should neither treat relativism as an explication of the nature
of truth nor as claims about meaning and certainly not about the claim
that whatever you believe is true. [75] In China, the perspectivist dimension of
his relativism rarely deals with visual or sense data perspective, e.g. the
fact that something appears oval from one angle and round from another.� The
formulation in the Zhuangzi deals with indexical perspective (the way
reference is indexed) value perspective that arises from being raised in or
committed to one scheme of shi-feithis-not this是 非(one
道 daoguide) rather than another. The theme is the relativity
of the obviousness of our action guiding distinctions.
A contemporary of Zhuangzi should not find plausible any interpretive
commitment to a "guru Zhuangzi." The usual development of the guru
theme in interpretation treats these relativist reflections as characterizing
the situation of the mere "ordinary person." [76] The text allegedly uses a
relativist analysis only to highlight what it is that guru insight somehow
transcends. [77] � Conventional,
relative, limited points of view trap ordinary people, but the perfected
Daoist sage transcends these to take a "rounded and complete" view.
Interpreters skip the step of showing how, in the face of Zhuangzi's relativist
and skeptical arguments, gurus manage this epistemic feat. If it is therapeutic
relativism, the therapy has been conveniently left out. This reading pictures
the Zhuangzi in a boastful, authoritarian stance�and one that assumes
a fundamental inequality. It is the posture of the Confucian justifying
rule of man. [78] � Rather than "no one knows the single
correct way to live," guru interpretations read it as saying "Only
I, Zhuangzi, know."
As in the case of skepticism, we can ask, what is the broader political, ethical,
or spiritual point of answering either "I doubt it" or "it depends"
to a question. Ultimately, a contemporary philosopher should still locate it
in the political realm�an argument for political neutrality and its associated
toleration of different concepts of the good life. More directly, the relativism
motivates the skepticism.� We cannot neutrally distinguish between our case
and that of someone with a rival dao making an equally confident and
"obvious" judgment that conflicts with ours. The skeptical outcome,
in turn, motivates the liberal political stance.
[79]
The relativism, like the skepticism, is broad in scope. The target of
relativist analysis is the dependency of our dao and our practical interpretation
of it on accidental facts of our upbringing and past. The linguistic focus of
the Zhuangzi's relativism of reference derives from the indexical analysis
of shi-feithis-not this是 非 which figures so
centrally in the account of 道 daoguide and Zhuangzi's
appeal to the relativism of acceptability (可 keassertible
). To decide what a term should "pick out" when executing a dao,
we appeal to our past training and practice. The linguistic texts use可
keassertible in their presentation and analysis of doubts
about reference of terms and assertability of larger strings. The Zhuangzi
observes that any existing linguistic practice creates its own assertability
conditions.
Daos: where can we go and they not be? Language: where can it
exist and not be acceptable? (4/2/25)
The focus on linguistic practices, acceptable ways to deploy distinctions etc.
nicely illustrates the Zhuangzi's characteristic analysis of ethical
disputes in ancient China. Mohists and Confucians dispute about burial practices.
Zhuangzi sees them as relying on different standards governing
their use of "good" or "not-good." One dao's standards
dictate using 'good' of such practices and the other does not. This linguistic
analysis of the issue links the Zhuangzi passages to Later-Mohist linguistics
and to Hui Shi's paradoxes and theses.
Hui Shi's relativist analyses of comparative terms (before/after, yesterday/today,
high/low, large/small, useful/useless and so forth) may have stimulated the
relativist lines of thinking in the Zhuangzi, but the Qiwulun arguments
broaden that focus dramatically.� It places Hui Shi's relativism of comparison
alongside the relativism of reference of indexicals�particularly 'this' (是
shithis:right) and 'that.' The indexical aspect of shi-feithis-not
this 是 非 thus broadens the scope of the relativist orientation.
The relativist points plays two different roles in undermining dogmatic claims
to knowing dao. One is that relativity plagues each step in the regress
of choosing the norms (the discourse daos). We think there is a correct
choice, but the choice appeals because of some other norm that we just happen
to have. Second, given a certain norm, relativity infects its interpretation
into action (its execution or performance). Where we distinguish correct
and wrong ways to do it, we depend on some interpretive norm. These two
are among the ways a way can be (in)constant. The denial that
ways are constant in one or all of these ways is the upshot of this relativist
line of thought.
A familiar instance of this kind of relativity is the relativity of historical
and cultural traditions. Any learned scheme may face both kinds of inconstancy.
We rely on some ground to prefer it to other historical traditions. We rely
on other norms to determine what counts as correctly following the tradition.
Relativist postures can also vary along a vague strength dimension. Strong
relativism would imply that the applicability of the term or the correctness
of the judgment depended entirely on that to which it was relative. Pure
subjectivism would be a strong kind of relativism. [80] Weak relativism would allow that the norm conditions contribute
to a classification or evaluation. Clearly, the relativism in these Chinese
terms is weak in this sense--judgments of large and small clearly have something
to do with the world as well as our standards of comparison. Judgments about
the reference of indexicals are in the same category.�
However, we can look at a different arena of "strength." How extreme
is the practical attitude one adopts in the face of recognizing the relativity
of shi-feithis-not this 是 非 judgments.
1. One might treat the
correct way to respond to the insight is to refuse to make any judgment. This
is what I characterize as the anti-language response (perhaps represented by
Hui Shi).� Since the distinctions are relative to our context of judgment, they
must be radically misleading. Reality has no distinctions.
As I noted, a philosopher could and should read the Zhuangzi passages
as rejecting any such argument for silence as the correct relativist posture.
We should read the text in awareness of the Mohist arguments against anti-language
and anti-distinctions conclusions. The story of the pipes of heaven (human speech
is as natural as bird twittering) together with the sheer delight in language
play evident throughout the text also suggest the response is too strong.
2. A slightly weaker
version may allow us to make a judgment, but not to defend it or claim that
it (or any judgment) is right and others wrong. This seems to be the posture
of Shen Dao and, again, a contemporary philosophical reader would reject this
reading where it was not explicitly stated. The text seems to reject such a
posture as being confused about the interrelation of "man" and 天
tiannature:sky.� By nature we make shi-feithis-not
this 是 非 judgments and rejecting them, as the Later Mohists
have shown, is incoherent.
3. A second "strong"
conclusion goes in the opposite Direction. It is not that our judgments are
wrong, but that all of them are right--anything goes.� Every judgment or conclusion
really has a ". . . from this perspective" rider attached.� There
are hints of this posture in the text on some issues. All language is 可
keassertible if some actual practice licenses it.�
Our conclusion that there are authentic-inauthentic or right-wrong is a trick
of "small accomplishments" or "elaboration."�
A reader with background in the linguistic analysis of the period could easily
find these passages making the important claim that the key term of that analysis,
可 keassertible, is strongly relativistic in this way.�
However, the Gaptooth dialogue (on page 28 ) and Zhuangzi's refutation of Hui
Shi's monism should warn us against careless inference from this point. It does
not entail that there is a perspective from which all language is可 keassertible.�
The perspective of 天� tiannature:sky� fails since nature
makes no shi-feithis-not this是 非 or� 可
keassertible judgment. From any actual perspective from which
we make such judgments, we will find some language not acceptable.� The Zhuangzi
is more careful on this point than are most commentators.
We可 keassertible from可 keassertible
and deny可 keassertible from a denying 可 keassertible.
Daos take shape as we "walk" them. 4/2/33
� This sound line of development first surfaces in the Mohist Canon
[81] against schools who present their 道 daoguide
as right because it is 天 tiannature's:sky's
dao.� All the existing 道 daoguides are natural
in virtue of being actual but Zhuangzi rejects the 'natural' to 'acceptable'
inference. [82] � Judgments of what is 可 keassertible
belong to the realm of renhuman not 天� tiannature:sky.
If we understand the relation of renhuman and 天 tiannature:sky�
we should see that 天 tiannature:sky� is not a normative
authority.
In rejecting this strong relativist posture that all 道 daoguides
are correct, we resist reading Zhuangzi's relative analysis of the dependency
of knowledge on norms and context into the semantic content of the judgment
itself. That is, the content of the dependent judgment does not have
a dependency rider. [83] The
judgment "this is an ox" is both causally and rationally dependent,
but it is distinct from the judgment "this is an ox from-my-point-of-view."
The relativity affects our basis for the judgment, but not its content.
If the relativism had this implication, then it would amount to denying that
we ever disagree. A contemporary philosophical reading would find no sound reason
to infer from these Zhuangzi passages that we do not really disagree.
The text presents it as a problem that our appeals to authorities and
other standards cannot neutrally resolve these disagreements.
4. A related but slightly
weaker conclusion is that all 道 daoguides are equal.�
The problem here is that 'equal' is an evaluative term and the judgment that
two things are equal appeal to some norm. [84] What might be justified is that all are equally天 tiannature:sky
.� However, a competent ancient Chinese philosopher should not make the further,
familiar mistake that presupposes the Confucian view of 天� tiannature:sky�
as an authority. The conclusion, apparently shared by Later Mohists and
Daoists,
is that 天 tiannature:sky� (contra Mozi and Mencius)
is not a normative standard. Norms come from 道 daoguides. [85]
5. I therefore construe
the Zhuangzi text as drawing a still weaker conclusion. It would accept, on
pain of being embroiled in an anti-language paradox, that we are permitted to
make judgments and to "deem" ourselves right in doing so.� Still,
we acknowledge that in our deeming, we have depended on some other norm that
we acquired "accidentally" (that we acquired in happening to be raised
and exposed to one of many possible paths).� We are not so confident as to make
us stop listening to and discussing with others or to warrant using coercion
to eliminate other daos. We accept that someone may be right (metaphysical realism),
that if two conflict, not both can be right and, trivially, accept the answer
we in fact accept. However, in acknowledging the relativity (dependency) of
our grounds or warrant for that judgment (or in appreciating the arbitrary historical-causal
source of our view), we adopt a modest epistemic posture�mild skepticism. Thus,
we can continue to discuss and seek to persuade (or be persuaded) from some
common basis. Alternatively, we can choose to be tolerant and agree to disagree.
Taking the relativism alongside the skepticism suggests that we do treat our
shi-feithis-not this 是 非 judgments themselves
as detached from dependence on our grounds or norms. We, thus, really do
disagree when we offer different answers and, at most, one of us can be correct.
This is what makes it worthwhile listening to others' extended views.� The relativism
explains why we disagree but does not remove the disagreement. Limiting relativism
in this way both motivates the skepticism (which would otherwise disappear)
and furthers the implicit political goal of tolerating disagreement, sharing
and respectful communication as a means of improving and enriching our respective
ways of life. This is crucial to Zhuangzi's pointed and consistent parody of
the Confucian bias that freaks and cripples (especially those who authorities
have mutilated to punish them) lack 德 �devirtuosity.
Suppose You and I have a dispute about a distinction (辯
biandistinction dispute) If you win and not I, are you really是
shithis:right and am I 非feinot-this:wrong?
If I win and you not, am I really是 shithis:right and
are you 非feinot-this:wrong?� Is one 是 shithis:right
and one 非feinot-this:wrong? Are both是 shithis:right
and both非feinot-this:wrong? If we cannot know this
between us, isn't everyone similarly in this kind of darkness?�� Whom could
we get to correct us? If we found someone like you to rectify the situation,
since he agreed with you, how could he correct us? If we found someone like
me to rectify the situation, since he agreed with me, how could he correct us?
If we found someone different from you and me to rectify us, since he was different
from both, how could he correct us? If we found someone who agreed with you
and me to rectify us, since he agreed with both of us, how could he correct
us? Therefore, neither you nor I nor other humans can resolve our dispute. Could
we find anything else to depend on? 7/2/85-90
We can raise a question at each reason giving norm level.� We can ask, discuss
and really disagree about what the correct norm to use to settle this
issue is. Indeed, we could. If we did, the content of the answer to that
question would be non-relative though our judgment about it would depend on
still other standards. We may now agree on those standards (and that is useful)
but, as the Gaptooth passage notes, such agreement would not mean we are right.�
Our judgment about our shared judgment would continue to be dependent.
We depend on 道 daoguide (norms) all the way up (and
down!). At any level we can encounter a real disagreement which may
be difficult or impossible to resolve because it signals our coming to the
issue with different 道 daoguides.�
What the relativism in the Zhuangzi explicitly denies is the Confucian-Mohist
assumption that the appeal to norms can come to an end at 天 tiannature:sky.
[86] To borrow a modern formula, no fact of the matter settles our disputes
about ways of life. There may be facts of the matter about whether historically
the dispute simmers down, reaches a synthesis, or just disappears as the
ways of life evolve within extant populations. No such fact, however, makes
the surviving one correct. Correct is an irreducibly normative matter.
That judgment can only be made by appeal to some norm�and 天 tiannature:sky�
is not a norm-authority. Only a dao can play that role. This, again,
is the sound sense in which Daoism privileges dao over 天� tiannature:sky.
The way in which relativism and skepticism are combined then schematically
follows its pattern in the West. We are skeptical about our judgments because
we appreciate the relativity of the grounds on which they depend. In the Chinese
case, the judgments are the 辯 biandistinction dispute�
and shi-feithis-not this 是 非 assignments. The
set of those judgments and the norms presupposed by them make up our rival 道
daoguides. Our experience of awakening or insight is typically
accompanied by a sense of confidence relative to what we "knew" before.
Given, however, the repetition of that kind of "waking" and our awareness
that others (including those who disagree with us) has gone through a similar
series of illuminations should give us epistemic pause--a relatively negative
or modest assessment of our cognitive accomplishments. Many or most schemes
of norms are the products of "emerging" from such insights as they
are stored up in our 成 chengprejudices 心 xinheart-mind
that "grows" along with the body.
Political philosophers will find the rest familiar turf. It is the context
of the normative theory of justice. Liberal justice addresses how we structure
society's basic institutions (the constitution) in a way that is neutral
among differing conceptions of the good life, different comprehensive guiding
views (religious, moral or philosophical) and ways of life.� Liberal theorists
argue that societies should adopt institutional structures that maximize freedom,
allow, and even encourage tolerance of different ways of life.
Much of this modern political theory rests similarly on a kind of mild skepticism.
[87] � While not implying that we abandon or stop advocating our own conception
of the good, it acknowledges that we have little reason to suppose that we can
rationally convince those with a different comprehensive view. We are
less than confident that we can prove the superiority of our way of life starting
from their norms. We accept that we cannot marshal arguments that should
convince all others to adopt our way of life. At the same time, we clearly recognize
that their arguments have not convinced us and are not showing any capacity
to do so. The skepticism does not rest on discovering anything wrong
about our way of life.
The politically motivated doubt is weak in the way Zhuangzi's is. We
doubt provability-to-the-other but that gives us no reason to abandon
our own way of life. Nor do we have reason to live with a gnawing, occurrent
doubt about how we live. We need not keep ourselves only weakly committed to
it or be on the verge of giving it up. [88] We need not cease caring about or advocating
it. Nor need we passively accept, based on this weak skepticism, the elimination
of our way of life by others. We do not face any obvious Hitler counter-example.
When we reflect correctly on relativistic skepticism, we should risk no undermining
of commitment other than agreeing to abandon prejudice, intolerance and
repression.
The problem with a full extrapolation of this modern theory of justice context
to the Zhuangzi is that, along with 'sentences' and 'truth', it is clearly
hard to find any neat counterpart of 'justice' in ancient Chinese political
theory. The paradigm political theories, Confucianism, Mohism and Legalism,
typically address nothing resembling constitutional structure at any deeper
level than Mozi's Hobbes-like justification of the wise ruling-elder. The chief
task of political theory, as the community delivered it to Zhuangzi, is how
to identify the wise leader who can correctly choose to impose a single way
of life on all.
Clearly, then the contextual point of the Zhuangzi's skepticism is precisely
that we should not attempt to do any such thing. No such person exists and we
should give up acting as if he/she does. There are no sages in the Confucian
or Mohist sense. Skepticism about ways of life in the context of ancient
Chinese political theory is skepticism of government--an argument for anarchy. [89] The delivered conception of
government in ancient China is intrinsically hostile to liberal neutrality and
intolerant of diversity of ways of life (道 daoguides).
If the purpose of government is to pick and impose a dao on the whole society,
then, Zhuangzi correctly concludes, government has no value�I will drag my tail
in the mud. [90]
Allinson, R. (1988) "On the Origin of the Relativistic Thesis for Interpretations
of the Chuang-tzu" Han Hs�e Yen Chiu v.� n. p. 275-298
___________. (1989) "On the Question of Relativism in the Chuang-tzu"
Philosophy East and West v. 39 n. 1 p. 13-26
Alt, Wayne (1991) "Logic and Language in the Chuang-tzu" Asian
Philosophy v. 1 n. 1 p. 61-76
Ames, Roger and Hall, David (1987). Thinking Through Confucius. Albany:
State University of New York Press.
Barry, Brian (1995). Justice as Impartiality. New York:� Oxford University
Press.
Birdwhistell, Anne D. (1984) "Knowledge Heard and Seen:The Attempt in
Early Chinese Philosophy to Analyze Experiential Knowledge" Journal
of Chinese Philosophy v. 11 n. 1 p. 67-82
Blackburn, Simon (1984). Spreading The Word: Groundings in the Philosophy of
Language. Oxford:� Clarendon Press.
Brandom, Robert B. (1994). Making it Explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Chinn, Ewing Y. (1997) "Zhuangzi and relativistic scepticism." Asian
Philosophy v. 7 n. 3 p. 207-221
___________. (1998) "The Natural Equality of All Things" Journal
of Chinese Philosophy v. 25 n. 4 p. 471-482
Cook, Scott (1997) "Zhuang Zi and his carving of the Confucian ox."
Philosophy East and West v. 47 n. 4 p. 521-554
Eno, Robert (1990). The Confucian Creation of Heaven. Buffalo: SUNY
Series in Chinese Philosophy and Culture.
__________ (1996) "Cook Ding's Dao and the Limits of Philosophy"
In Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J, ed. Essays on Skepticism, Relativism
and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and
Culture. Pp. 127-151.
Goldman, Alvin (1986). Epistemology and Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Graham, Angus (1978). Later Mohist Logic, Ethics and Science. Hong Kong
and London:� Chinese University Press.
___________ (1981). Chuang tzu: The Inner Chapters. London:� Allen &
Unwin.
___________ (1985) "Review of Language and Logic in Ancient China"
Harvard Journal of Asian Studies v. 45 n. 2 p. 692-70
___________ (1990). Studies in Chinese Philosophy and Philosophical Literature.
Albany: State University of New York Press.
Grandy, Richard (1973) "Reference Meaning and Belief" Journal
of Philosophy v.� n. p. 439-452
Hansen, Chad (1983). �A Tao of Tao in Chuang Tzu.� In Mair, Victor, ed. Experimental
Essays on Chuang-tzu. Honolulu:� University of Hawaii Press. 24 55.
___________ (1983). Language and Logic in Ancient China. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
___________ (1985). "Chinese Language, Chinese Philosophy, and 'Truth',"
Journal of Asian Studies, 491-519.
___________ (1992). A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought. New York:� Oxford
University Press.
Hollis, Martin and Steven Lukes ed. (1982). Rationality and Relativism.
Oxford:� Basil Blackwell.
Ivanhoe, Philip J. (1991) "Zhuangzi's Conversion Experience" Journal
of Chinese Religions v. 19 n. p. 13-25
___________. (1993) "Skepticism, Skill and the Ineffable Tao" Journal
of the American Academy of Religion v. 61 n. 4 p. 639-654
___________. (1996). �Was Zhuangzi a Relativist?.� In Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe
Philip J, ed. Essays on Skepticism, Relativism and Ethics in the Zhuangzi.
Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and Culture. 197-214.
Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J ed. (1996). Essays on Skepticism, Relativism
and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and
Culture.
Kjellberg, Paul (1994) "Skepticism, Truth and the Good Life: A Comparison
of Zhuangzi and Sextus Empiricus
___________ (1996). �Sextus Empiricus, Zhuangzi and Xunzi on "Why be Skeptical".�
In Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J, ed. Essays on Skepticism, Relativism
and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and
Culture. 1-25.
Lukes, Stephen (1982). �Relativism in Its Place.� In Hollis, Martin and Steven
Lukes, ed. Rationality and Relativism. Oxford:� Basil Blackwell. 261-305.
Maspero, Henri (1971). Le Taoisme et les religions chinoises. Paris:
Gallimard.
Miller, Richard W. (1996) "The Norms of Reason" Philosophical
Review v. 105 n. 2 p. 205-245
Nivison, David (1991). �Hsun Tzu and Chuang Tzu.� In Rosemont, Henry, Jr.,
ed. Chinese Texts and Philosophical Contexts: Essays Dedicated to A. C. Graham.
La Salle, IL:� Open Court. 129-142.
Pfister, Lauren (1990) "Clues to the life and academic Achievements of
one of the most Famous Nineteenth Century European Sinologists" Journal
of the Hong Kong British Royal Asiatic Society v. 30 n. p. 180-218
___________ (1991) "New Dimensions in the Study of the Works of James
Legge (1815-1897): Part I & II." Sino-Western Cultural Relations
Journal v.� n. p. 29-50 & 33
Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Raphels, Lisa (1996). �Skeptical Strategies in the Zhuangzi and Theaetetus.�
In Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J, ed. Essays on Skepticism, Relativism
and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and
Culture. 26-49.
Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
___________ (1993). Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Schwartz, Benjamin (1985). The World of Thought in Ancient China. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Schwitzgebel, Eric (1996). �Zhuangzi's Attitude toward Language and His Skepticism.�
In Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J, ed. Essays on Skepticism, Relativism
and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in Chinese Philosophy and
Culture. 68-96.
Sellars, Wilfred (1963). �Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind.� In
Sellars,
Wilfred, ed. Science, Perception and Reality. London:� Routledge &
Kegan Paul. .
___________ (1963). Science, Perception and Reality. London:� Routledge
& Kegan Paul.
Sperber, Dan (1982). �Appararently Irrational Beliefs.� In Hollis, Martin and
Steven Lukes, ed. Rationality and Relativism. Oxford:� Basil Blackwell.
149-180.
Tsai Chih Chung (1997). The Dao of Zhuangzi. Garden City, NY: Anchor
Books (Doubleday and Co.).
Van Norden, Bryan V. (1996) "Competing interpretations of the Inner Chapters
of the 'Zhuangzi.'" Philosophy East and West v. 46 n. 2 p. 247-269
Wong, David (1984) "Taoism and the Problem of Equal Respect" Journal
of Chinese Philosophy v. 11 n. p. 165-183
Yearley, Lee, (1996) "Zhuangzi's Understanding of Skillfulness and the
Ultimate Spiritual State" in Kjellberg Paul and Ivanhoe Philip J, ed. Essays
on Skepticism, Relativism and Ethics in the Zhuangzi. Buffalo: SUNY Series in
Chinese Philosophy and Culture. 68-96.
[1] One obvious example is Allinson's treatment of
Zhuangzi as engaged in "spiritual transformation" and another is
the quest by Graham (1981) (who credits Lee Yearly with the idea), Nivison
(1991) and Ivanhoe (1991) to identify Zhuangzi's "conversion experience."�
Ivanhoe, in a helpful survey and analysis, traces the theme back to Maspero
(1971).
[2] These include Raphals (1996), Chinn (1997 &
1998), Kjellberg (1994 &1996), Van Norden (1996) and Ivanhoe (1993 &
1996) Allinson (1988 & 1989) and Schwitzgebel (1996). Ivanhoe and Kjellberg�
(1996) is a� helpful collection of objections to skeptical or relative interpretations.�
Schwitzgebel expresses in strongest language a common theme in these articles
when he says "although Zhuangzi argues for radical skepticism, he does
not sincerely subscribe to it." Kjellberg and Ivanhoe propose the helpful
notion of "therapeutic" skepticism (relativism) to describe the
common interpretive theme that recurs throughout their edited collection.
[3] My experience stems
from inner reflection on the success of my critics in characterizing my argument.
Among the authors who directly address my position, the one who most egregiously
distorts it, states it competently and correctly in barely 15% of the sentences
devoted to describing my view.� Given the disparity in our disciplines and
training, I can only worry I might do as badly.� If will leave it to the discerning
reader to assess whether my analysis successfully captures the force of any
particular writer's position. If it does not, I willingly plead guilty to
constructing a straw man and have only the comfort that I have not accused
any particular writer of being that straw man. The reader certainly is entitled
to draw amusement from the difficulty we have understanding each other while
we pose as interpreters of a philosopher as far removed from all of us as
Zhuangzi is.
[4] Raphals argues that skepticism per se is
incoherent and Kjellberg & Ivanhoe appear to endorse that in their introduction
as they say [strong] skepticism "is generally acknowledged as self-refuting
since . . . we cannot know even that we know nothing." (1996:xv) Among
philosophers, by contrast, although skeptics are far from the majority, Stroud
(1968) is widely acknowledged as having shown that past attempts to defeat
the skeptic on purely analytic (logical or conceptual) grounds fail.
Others (Van Norden, Chinn, and Ivanhoe) claim that any combination of relativism
and skepticism is incoherent. Note that if we accept the interpretive principle
and the disabling definition, we could conclude that no one in the
history of world philosophy was ever a skeptic (or relativist skeptic).�
Surely, we should extend that interpretive charity to Western philosophers
as generously as we should to Chinese philosophers.�� Van Norden and Ivanhoe
give definitions of relativism that virtually entail that relativism is self-refuting.
Most distinguish between a "good" or "common-sense" versions
and "radical" "strong" "extreme" or "philosophical"
versions--for which they give the self-refuting formulae.
[5] Given this commitment to coherence in interpretation,
I will argue that step 4 presents an ironic example of the contrast between
the two principles (in section�� I.E.1 .). The therapeutic step clearly violates
the community coherence principle.
[6] See Hansen (1978 and 1992).
[7] Some of my own interpretive prior formulations
may have invited this mistake. In personal conversation repeatedly and in
his (1991), Ivanhoe appeals to my 1983 for methodological support. I emphasized
there the principle of humanity as a principle of choice among interpretive
hypotheses.� I formulated it as a principle of preferring the more rationally
coherent interpretation since coherence helps us explain a person's beliefs.
But I also expanded that immediately by arguing that we explain a sentence
by showing its coherence in the context of a section, the section in a book,
the book in the writer's work, the writer's work a school's development and
the school in a philosophical tradition. That formulation, though holistic
in spirit, was unfortunate in suggesting that there was a separate book-level
at which the virtue of coherence was separable from the holistic context Quine-Davidson
emphasize.
[8] Grandy's (1973) formulation is that the imputed
pattern of relations among beliefs, desires and the world be a similar to
our own as possible. We would want the pattern of relations to include those
to our sensory apparatus, childhood training, etc.� What should be "like
our own" would include the tendency to believe and utter incoherent things
that we learn in Sunday school and the like. Thinking of the principle of
humanity as a matter of access places coherence in the right kind of context.
We can explain access to certain beliefs on perception grounds and others
as natural or obvious inferences from other beliefs we attribute to them.
Coherence thus becomes a part of the explanation of access to beliefs. See
Blackburn (1984) for an extended account of the "virtues" appropriate
for the principle of humanity.
[9] Here I leave aside, of course, Quinian worries
about the metaphysical shape our awareness of such animals takes. It is possible
to argue that a community accesses cows as temporal slices or masses, but
a theory that does not needs no elaborate justification.
[10] The plausibility of a "story" may,
of course, depend on what the interpreter or her audience takes to be true
about these objects, human psychology, historical facts, and so forth. If
one believes that God "contacts" humans regularly in some way and
would similarly have "contacted" Ancient Chinese thinkers, then
a different story about the reference of the term 天 tiannature:sky�
would seem plausible. The same goes for psychological terms like 'belief'
and moral terms like 'justice'.� Arguments for any innate conceptual structure
or religious "instinct" in humans would work . . . for those who
accept them.� The first interpreters in China assumed God's existence was
rationally inescapable. This solved, for them, the problem of access to the
same God as long as they credited Chinese philosophers with
full rationality. (Thanks to Lauren Pfister who helped me see this point in
conversation about James Legge. See Pfister 1990 and 1991)
[11] I am drawing heavily on Brandom 1994 here.
[12] Hansen (1992).� It is commonplace among Sinologists
to refer to words as "Confucian terms" or "Daoist terms"
implying that anyone who uses it is a Confucian or "borrows" it�as
if factions could own bits of Chinese language. Alternately, they speak of
writers giving Confucian, Daoist or Mohist "meanings" to the terms
they borrow from each other. Since interpretation is holistic, this argument
does not entail that we can never postulate such a case�only that postulating
it should make sense of more of their discourse than it makes nonsense of
it.� My worry was that the impression of Chinese philosophy as nonsense is
a product of interpreters making too much of the disputation nonsensical in
this way in order to make the bulk of assertions (Confucianism) come out "true
in Chinese". Meaning change hypotheses are central to this strategy because
they make the objection of contemporary Chinese philosophical opponents irrelevant.
[13] I do not deny that the Zhuangzi might have been
read differently by people without philosophical training in ancient China,
just as it is today. If there was a sect of Huang-Lao worship, it may well
have read this text as in ways that lacked philosophical insight and subtlety.
That is not sufficient reason for us to adopt such norms in our interpretation
though it is a historically authentic basis for making interpretive claims.
[14] Competence may include having relevant specialized
knowledge. People who can read but do not know the field may not understand
certain passages.� Thus, the competent reader, on the present assumptions,
must be philosophically informed.� On some other assumptions, he may need
religious training etc. In principle, readers with different competencies�
could read the same essay differently. This would lead to interpretive relativism
� there would be more than one correct, historically authentic (where the
rival scorekeepers are both ancient Chinese but of different training and
background) interpretation of a phrase. Notice that we are forced to this
possibility by taking a community or audience view of correct interpretation,
rather than an authorial intention view. Since communities can be sliced up
in different ways and deference to linguistic authority may be controversial
within a community, interpretive pluralism cannot be ruled out.
[15] Note that failing to interpreting me charitably
is not my main complaint against certain critics. What is most disturbing
is a consistent pattern of attributing their sophomoric conceptions, fallacious
inferences and incoherent formulations to me�often with explicit claims
like ". . .in Hansen's own terms . . ." followed by his own paraphrase
involving his specious inference." (Ivanhoe 1996:197) Chinn is similarly
negligent in actually putting quotes around his views while attributing them
to me--sans citations, of course. (Chinn 1997:213).
[16] My defense, in turn, would be to note that competent
professional philosophers should not find the positions mutually excluding.
Whether or not my attribution is incoherent would then depend on which of
us is right about the inferential potential of the English phrase �relativistic
skeptic� in philosophical discourse. Here, again, we see the linguistic division
of labor at work.
[17] See Hansen 1992:277-280.
[18] I hope the "informed-audience" focus
will deter interpreters from the interpretive assertion I call psychic-identification.�
"Although Zhuangzi says X, he really wants us to believe Y."
That kind of "interpretation" is sometimes appropriate, e.g., to
explain a verbally inept, intimate friend or family member (or politically
popular president). I take it no modern interpreter is in a position to take
that posture toward Zhuangzi--unless, of course, he is a reincarnation! The
focus on the public meaning of the expressions found in the text still leaves
leeway for judgment since interpretation remains normative. An account
of meaning is an account of what accepting the text entails about what
one' ought further to accept (and reject) given the norms enshrined
in some ancient Chinese community's language practices.
[19] Particularly the Qiwulun. I need not
deny that there is less evidence of such contact in other parts of the book.
I accept the current textual theories of multiple authorship of this text.
I would claim, however, that much of the rest of the book could have been
read in ways consistent with the arguments in �Qiwulun� by informed philosophers.
Few, if any, of them force a mystical or religious reading on us.
[20] Sinologists chuckle at us when they suspect
that philosophically inclined interpreters are more interested in what Zhuangzi
should have said than what he did say. Our point here is more subtle
than they think--having said what he did say, we explain its meaning
by theorizing about what else he should accept in virtue of
having said it--what saying it commits him to. We do not make the judgment
by simply imposing our judgment of what is true.
[21] Notice that there is no sound prohibition against
"imposing" some Western theory or concept on Chinese thinkers simply
because it is Western. The justified prohibition is against using concepts,
theories or arguments without making a plausible argument that the resources
for them were available to ancient Chinese thinkers.� Again,no such prohibition
applies to modern concepts or theories.� Ancient Greek thought or enlightenment
European thought would be a better framework for comparative work only if
we successfully argued that it was presuppositionless or consisted of �natural�
first philosophical thoughts.
[22] I reject, that is, objections that a theme in
one passage �conflicts in tone� with something written elsewhere in a text
or �seems to suggest a different attitude.�� No plausible interpretive seems
to require tone consistency.�
[23] I will focus on passages that even critics of
skeptical interpretations generally accept as expressing skeptical or relativistic
attitudes. I will focus on the analysis of the kind of relativism or skepticism
implied in such passages.
[24] I appeal her to the tendency in Confucius' analects
to refer to "ritual" and "music" together as models of
action guidance. The implicit emphasis on aesthetic features of action judgment
and its relation to guidance is a common theme in discussions of Confucius,
see, for example, Hall and Ames (1987) and Eno (1990).
[25] These different aspects of dao account
for the alleged change of meaning that tradition associates with Daoism. Shen
Dao seems to have envisioned the actual course of action of the entire world
and called that "The Great Dao."� He then denied that it is normative�even
a clod of earth cannot miss it! I have questioned the assumption that other
alleged Daoists follow him in talking this way. Most seem to retain a normative
use of the term.
[26] For details, see my 1992 chapter on Mozi, especially
pages 115-121 and 124-128.
[27] Mozi: Against Aggressive Warfare (17) Harvard
Yenching 28/17/11-12.
[28] This is an important point often missed by commentators
who notice the similarities of Mozi's argument and that of Thomas Hobbes.�
See Schwartz (1985) and Hansen (1992) for an expression of the different views.
[29] The composition of the character zhenggovern
consists of zhengrectify and a radical meaning "to
beat."� Confucius contrasts guiding by zhenggoverning
with guiding by 禮 liritual in ways that suggest he
views it as the more coercive way to "correct" people.�
[30] Mozi "Universal Love" (16)
[31] Mozi "Agreement with the Superior"
(11) The neutrality analysis could continue in the face of this. The ruler
chooses other officials for their wisdom and ability. Both appeals to wisdom
and ability might be thought to be value neutral on the grounds that
the selection of the ruler appears to be a unanimous judgment as to
his wisdom. He carries out his task not by imposing his own shi-feithis-not
this 是 非 but by initiating the program of reporting up
and adjudicating down all the shi-feithis-not this 是
非 judgments. We may think of the resulting conception of the good as
the joint product of combining everyone's rival conceptions according to a
value-neutral, nearly ideal observer.
[32] Chapter 33, "The Social World" is
found in the "miscellaneous" chapters. It has a markedly more political
orientation than most of the inner chapter texts in which we find clear statements
of skepticism and relativism.
[33] When the social world is in disorder, worthies
and sages do not discern (appear?) and ethics is not unified. Many in the
social world examine a portion of it and regard themselves well. It is like
ear, eye, nose and mouth. Each has that which it can discern but they cannot
interchange. So the hundred schools with their crowd of skills, each has a
strength and there is a time when it is useful. Still, we should not fail
to be comprehensive. (The Zhuangzi Ch. 33)
[35] They sometimes talked about compound terms,
modification, and the effect on shuoexplanation and daodiscourse.�
In my view, the closest they came to sentential inference was in the Xiao
Qu (See Hansen 1983). For a contrary view, see Graham (1972).
[36] I do not address here another kind of knowledge
that is plainly a subject of discussion--knowing of. The Mohists describe
this as "contact knowledge."� See the excellent discussion in Birdwhistell
(1984).� I also discuss it in Hansen (1983).
[37] This is what I take to be the correct analysis
of the 以 . . . 為 . . . pattern in classical Chinese and the
related use of one place predicates as transitive verbs�to "white"
something is to treat it as "white" in attitude and action. See
my more complete analysis in Hansen 1992.
[38] There is an interesting counter-example in Zhuangzi's
"Happy Fish" discussion in which knowing that one knows becomes
fully sentential. Visual verbs (see, observe etc.) and speaking verbs (says,
quotes etc.) introduce sentential contexts so I should not claim that there
are no sentential contexts in ancient Chinese.� However, the concepts of belief,
desire and knowing do not normally take sentential form.
[39] I propose to detach mysticism from monism. 'Mystical'
typically attaches to 'experience'.� We may speak of mystical reality as the
content of a mystical experience.� Mysticism is a combination of an epistemological
and a linguistic thesis.� Mystics typically allege they have found a special
epistemological access to some content (typically metaphysical, religious
or practical).� They treat the content as incommunicable except by that special
access. Most assume the content is monist, but that is not entailed by
either the epistemic or the linguistic claims.
[40] Implicitly, then, I reject mysticism while embracing
monism. The Zhuangzi would not be claiming some special epistemic access
to the real world. It expresses skepticism about its own monistic conception
of the real world.� Its relative silence on metaphysical matters is appropriate.
[41] Noumenon-phenomenon parallels are more frequently
alleged. I am skeptical of these as well and align myself with the anti-dualist
analysis of Chinese thought, e.g., Ames and Hall (1987).
[42] This is a familiar illustration of chaos theory
as applied to meteorology.
[43] I say only "rough" counterparts because
I see little hint of the kinds of logical-semantic and grammatical considerations
that inspired Parmenides and in turn Plato and his successors among Western
mystics and idealists.
[44] I am thinking of the "ten theses"
quoted in the Zhuangzi Ch. 33 history of philosophy. The final one
is "love all thing-kinds pervasively; the cosmos is one dipody."�
Hui Shi's reasoning seems to rest on the relativist analysis of terms and
the illegitimate inference from the premise that our distinctions between
things are relative to our perspective to a conclusion that there are no distinctions
in reality. See my discussion in Hansen (1992:269-272).
[45] In a sense, Zhuangzi would not be skeptical
about contact knowledge (see fn. 36 ). His skepticism applies to how we distinguish,
classify and react to it but not that it is there and that we are in contact
with it in the course of our thinking and acting.
[46] I owe my classifications here to Goldman (1986).�
He is, of course, not responsible for my adaptation and application of them
to the quite different context of Chinese thought.
[47] In this division, I follow the helpful models
of Raphals, Kjellberg and Ivanhoe but with a more complex classification.
My main reservation about their approach apart from the difference in treating
the theme (see below), is that they tend to blur scope and strength
into a single classification like� "extreme" or "radical"
skepticism.
[48] The most prominent examples, I think, are Raphals
(1996) who distinguishes between skeptical recommendations, skeptical doctrines
and skeptical methods, and Kjellberg (1994 and 1996). They both draw on the
ancient Greek form of skepticism (See note 21
) where this explicit formulation of the problem can be found in the texts.
Raphals distinctions are helpful, but, as I argue below, I cannot see any
reason to think they force an exclusive choice on interpreters�even of Greek
skepticism. A Pyrrhonian could be committed to suspending judgment as important
for personal satisfaction and accompany that with a fully skeptical attitude
of doubt about our epistemic achievements.� When they say, "things are
equally indifferent, unmeasurable and inarbitrable" as Aristotle reports
Timon arguing. (Eusebius, Prep. Ev. 14.18.2-5, Long & Sedley) it
is not a claim about a state of mind, but the difficulty in knowing things.
By contrast, the recommendation endorsed by the therapeutic interpreters is
incoherent in a more objectionable way since a) it too would normally be delivered
as a judgment and b) it directly conflicts with its own content (i.e., we
don't need to appeal to a separate norm of assertion).� We can save the recommendation
analysis if we read it as "don't make any descriptive judgments
(i.e., evaluative judgments are acceptable)."� But that is an implausible
content given the motivation Raphals and Kjellberg appeal to.
[49] Raphals quotes or summarizes a good sample of
the skeptical passages in the Zhuangzi and concludes "Is Zhuangzi
a skeptic by doctrine? The evidence seems to refute this possibility."
How can we have such different evaluations of them? I suspect the answer lies
not in her contrast between recommendation and thesis, but between 'method'
and thesis.� She finds them evidence of "skeptical methods" but
not theses. She defines a skeptical method as "a question or inquiry
that leads to doubt."� Had she stopped there, any disagreement between
us would be purely verbal. Doubt about our knowing some subject matter is
what I call skepticism. The passages "lead to" such doubt.� They
are, ergo, arguments for skepticism.� However, she continues, "Its form
tends to reject or ignore a skeptical thesis, and tends to advocate, or at
least suggest, a skeptical recommendation." (Raphals 1996:28)� I see
no evidence for this step, and as argued above, it is not only incoherent,
but also known among ancient Chinese philosophers to be so.
[50] Attributing a spiritualist or psychic tranquillity
concern to the Zhuangzi must be hypothetical since, unlike the Phyrronian
model, it never directly presents that as the motivation of its skeptical
passages. The confidence interpreters have that they should find personal,
religious or spiritual growth themes in any work from this period is hard
to explain except as reading back in the traditional interpretive assumptions
that Daoism is a "personal religion."� Classical Confucianism and
Mohism are widely considered to have been dominated by a political and moral
focus. We should neither take our familiarity with such religious themes or
our association of religion with "primitive" or pre-scientific
thought as evidence that Chinese thinkers must have had such unexpressed
concerns.
[51] A theoretical discussion is in Ch. 2 (HY 4/2/32-5/2/38).
Graham treats 因yinbecause as "criterion"
which indeed captures one side of the ambiguity. The "shadow" passage
also has a dependency themes and uses待 daidepend�
The Zhuangzi Ch. 2 HY 7/2/92-4.
[52] Mozi �Against Fatalism�
[53] The Mozi discussions typically assume
that all three standards support their conclusions.
[54] Ivanhoe (1993) may have scope in mind when he
gives his account of four "forms" of skepticism.� His forms are
'sense', 'ethical', 'epistemological' and 'language'. Partly, he distinguishes
his epistemological from ethical on scope grounds--descriptive
statements v. normative ones. He defines ethical skepticism as "the belief
that there are no moral truths" in contrast to epistemological skeptics
who "do not deny that there are objective facts about the world. . .
they only deny that we can have reliable knowledge of those facts." The
former, obviously, is not an epistemological thesis, but a metaethical one.
Ivanhoe counts it as skepticism since "she would deny that we have or
can have true moral knowledge, since there is nothing for such knowledge to
be about." P. 641. See also his footnote on the same page.
[55] Yearley (1996:156) discusses this feature of
skepticism in the Zhuangzi using the familiar story of the lucky-unlucky
horse.
[56] This is slightly different from Western versions
what Goldman calls 'iterative skepticism' in that the classic Western use
of this argument would be formulated in terms of a requirement that to know,
one must know that she knows.� This is a strong requirement and the skepticism
is, ergo, a weak version. This passage, however, does not put such a requirement
on knowledge. It implicitly allows that we might know something without knowing
that we know it. It is still a weak version, therefore, but for a different
reason. It is technically not denying that we have knowledge. It suggest only
that our having knowledge might be "accidental." The accidental
element is not our coming to believe X, but our having acquired one of several
conceptions of knowledge.
[57] Confucius was, notoriously, the most modest
of the triumvirate of classical Confucians. Mencius and Xunzi both developed
extended accounts of how perspective-transcending knowledge was available
to well cultivated Confucians. It informs their shared view that ordinary
people can become sages.
[58] Many accounts focus on such skill stories. There
is much of value to be gained from these accounts, but they tend to preface
reference to skill with some adjective that makes it seem supernatural-- 'perfect',
'miraculous', 'ineffable' 'supreme', etc.� Cook (1997) following Eno speaks
about "perfect" mastery of skill. Van Norden (1996) similarly insists
the story of Cook Ding is in no way skeptical and calls such skill 'miraculous'
and takes its point to be that the sage can become "impervious to injury."
Van Norden credits Ivanhoe (1993) who also appeals to the skill stories to
reject skeptical interpretations. They illustrate what Ivanhoe calls the "profoundly
enhanced power" of the Way. Yearly, after a masterfully careful
discussion, infers that the implication of the skill stories is "
Skillful activity, then, clearly points to the highest spiritual state."
Eno's (1996) formulations are ambiguous--sometimes more constrained, e.g.,
"virtuoso skills" but others endorsing the common interpretation
that the stories entail " the ideal of the person whose perfect skills
have released him from the dualities of this and that." P. 135.� Then
Eno denies that Ding is perfect and concludes, cautiously and correctly, that
Zhuangzi only makes a "positive judgment" of such skill. I accept
that final claim, though Zhuangzi's positive judgment is qualified (see below)
and, in any case, is fully consistent with his skepticism. I deny that a competent
philosopher among Zhuangzi's contemporaries would be justified in using supernaturalism
to state the implications of such stories. Eno puts the point slightly differently
when he opines Zhuangzi may have known that with such skill cannot make you
survive a fall from a cliff!� He goes on to claim for Confucians the
posture that skill can reach perfection. (1996:164)
[59] The stories seldom illustrate re-conversion
to one's original position. Technically, a Zhuangzi should not claim that
when we leave one perspective for another that we know in any absolute way
that the old one was defective. We simply adopt a new perspective from which
we judge the old one wrong.
[60] What is also striking about the narrative context
of such references in the Qiwulun at least is that they all seem to
be introduced by a "student" question following directly on some
skeptical denial of the possibility of perfection. The question is obtuse
on its face�as if following an argument that perfection is impossible, he
raises his hand and asks "Yeah Prof, but what about a perfect person?"
The response in the Qiwulun is Zen-like. Instead of embarrassing him
by asking, "Were you listening just then?" it invites him to reflect
on "how could you possibly recognize 'perfect' if you saw it?" HY
6/2/71-3
[61] Graham's translation captures the point nicely:
"To recognize as complete or flawed is to have as model the Chao when
they play the zither; to recognize as neither complete nor flawed is to have
as a model the Chao when they don't play the zither." Ch. 2 HY5/2/43-7.
[62] HY 6/2/72 It is helpful to read such passages
alongside arguments against ideal observer ethical theories. When I am wondering
what to do, what relevance is the judgment of a being so unlike me as to be
incomprehensible? Chapter 6 has many examples of these themes.
[63] There is more, for example, in the Xunzi
"Rectifying Names" chapter where we find a sketchy and troublesome
account the roles of the sense organs and the 心 xinheart-mind.
Notice that even if interpreted as motivating sense skepticism (see my denial
in Hansen 1992) passages such as the butterfly dream do not work like appeals
to illusion, to show the fallibility of the senses.� The appeal to
dreaming would have to be about the fallibility of our former judgments
about when information is coming from the senses or not.
[64] This formulation is deliberately ambiguous.
See my explanation in Hansen (1992).
[65] Especially the Xinshu [ch 37] and Neiye
[Ch. 38] of the Guanzi and the more "absolutist" sections of the
Xunzi e.g., "Dispelling Obsessions" [ch. 21].
[66] Ivanhoe (1993 & 1996) is an excellent example.�
Viewing the argument in terms of "human limitation" furthers the
strategy of attributing to Zhuangzi a claim that Daoists have transcended
those limitations and achieved perfect knowledge. The actual dependency argument
undercuts any such claim. All shi-feithis-not this 是
非 attributions depend on other normative standards.� We presuppose
norms all the way down; there is no shortcut via either metaphysics (transcendence)
or epistemology (intuition).
[67] Ivanhoe (1993:648) acknowledges there is skepticism
in the text, proceeds to deny that Zhuangzi is a skeptic then avers "He
is an epistemological skeptic, but only of a certain kind of knowledge, i.e.,
intellectual knowledge. He is not at all skeptical about intuitive knowledge."
(Italics in original).� He associates his distinction in knowledge types (intellectual/intuitive)
with the contrast between propositional knowledge and knowing-how and then,
identifies the latter with linguistic skepticism. He notes that Zhuangzi
is ultimately led to laugh at his position.
[68] We have our own culture wars, of course and,
as I noted above, religious or romantic opponents of reason and philosophy
may have different standards of interpretation and use of texts.
[69] If one's textual theory held that a single author
sincerely and seriously asserted both, it would� be evidence that that author
was inconsistent.� It would not force us to choose between which of the two
positions was the correct one to attribute to him.
[70] I discussed the "advice" that seems
to follow from the Zhuangzi analysis in my 1992:299-303.
[71] Some critics object to the extreme toleration
implied by this approach. One version is what I call the "Hitler"
objection. The texts from this period seem to neither contemplate nor address
evils of such obvious magnitude. Still, we can easily imagine how a competent
student of Zhuangzi could answer. The answer would track the argument a modern
liberal could offer of the principle of neutrality toward different conceptions
of the good. It need not require toleration of ways of life that cannot participate
in an open dispute of daos on the basis the kind of equality that the
mild skepticism requires. The judgment of what daos are worth listening
to must be made from here, so must the judgment of what daos to tolerate
and what to fight against. The awareness of our fallibility in such judgments
should mainly raise the threshold of when we accept coercing and killing people
to prevent the spread of their dao.
[72] Hansen 1985 and 1992.
[73] Ivanhoe (1996:198) deduces this conclusion from
his formulation of relativism and attributes it to me. "Since there are
no grounds to anyone's choice, anything goes and equally well." Chinn's
is "all the conflicting daos in question are in principle equally admissible"
(Chinn 1977:209--again attributed to me!),� The "everything is right"
position, however, may be the implication of a familiar traditional reading
of Daoism�slightly modifying Shen Dao's position. Eno illustrates this interpretation.
(Eno 1996:133)
[74] We see a similar pattern in Western skepticism
where skepticism of the senses is motivated by examples of the relativity
of sense perception.
[75] See Van Norden's formulation (1996:247-9). Chinn
(1997) has a similar formulation.� He calls Zhuangzi a perspectivist, but
not a relativist, but I am unclear how much his considered interpretation
diverges from mine. His entire argument is an argument against his own account
of relativism, not mine despite his frequent and unjustified attribution to
me. "A relativist like Zhuangzi, on the other hand, as Hansen (sic.)
would have it, denies the very possibility (and even meaningfulness) of objective
truth. Zhuangzi, if he is indeed a relativist, cannot think that anyone can
have a true belief about the world, in the sense of a belief that 'corresponds'
to something that exists independent of anyone's conceptual framework. Otherwise
he cannot maintain that one shihs [what] someone else can with equal justification,
fei." (p. 210-12). I, of course, deny that Zhuangzi affirmed or denied
anything about truth or belief. I certainly never formulated
my description of his relativism in such terms. I see no reason cited in Chinn's
article for thinking a competent philosopher from Zhuangzi's period would
have inferred anything about truth from Zhuangzi's familiar claims
about relativity in justifying shi-feithis-not this是
非 judgments. When Chinn encounters the more detailed account of my
view in Hansen (1992) he calls it a "striking reversal. . .clearly incompatible
with . . .Hansen's earlier essay" (Chin 1997:213).� Of course, what it
is incompatible with is his interpretation of my earlier essay.� He continues
by characterizing my earlier view of relativism as a "subjective point
of view" (quotes in original�but, again, they are Chinn's words, and
words I consistently not only eschewed but warned against) and then Chinn
formulates my earlier position with a reference to an "unknowable
reality," i.e., clearly consistent with the view I take in my 1992.
[76] Ivanhoe, for example, acknowledges that the
Zhuangzi contains relativist passages, but divines somehow (unexplained)
that "their purpose" is therapeutic and underpins the difference
between "our scheming minds" and some "intuitive, ineffable"
knowledge. (Ivanhoe 1993:699)
[77] Ivanhoe (1993:645) is the only example I know
who has implied that the relativism in the Zhuangzi is "spiritual
therapy."� His is perhaps the origin of this now popular strategy for
dealing with the Zhuangzi's skepticism.
[78] Credit to Eno for recognizing this important
distinction. See note 58 above.
[79] David Wong (1984) offers a closely related argument
deriving norms of equal respect more directly from the relativism implicit
in Daoism. I agree with Barry (1995) that we need some skepticism to finally
justify neutrality among ways of life in political matters, but I agree with
Wong that the "thought experiments" in Daoism where we learn to
view things from the other's point of view does help motivate treating others
as equals when we disagree fundamentally in our comprehensive views.
[80] Van Norden (1996:249-50) confuses relativism
and subjectivism in his formulations. He translates ethical relativism as
"certain ethical facts are dependent upon my own opinions" and illustrates
the analysis with this example "'Murder is wrong' is true (relative to
me) just in case I believe murder is wrong."
[81] Graham (1972:244) highlights the emergence of
this perspective in the Mohist Canon. He argues that it leads the Later Mohists
to abandon altogether the idea of appealing to 天 tiannature:sky�
in justifying their 道 daoguide.
[82] I take this to be the implication of the "pipes
of heaven" passage. 3/2/3-9.
[83] This confusion is reflected in Ivanhoe's (1996:198)
inference that Zhuangzi's position "provides no ethical guidance whatsoever.
. . . no standards by which we might judge a given action as morally good
or bad. I could still treat other people in a brutish, crudely exploitive,
and self-serving manner. I could feel justified in doing so not because I
believed that my actions are somehow grounded in some deeper truth about the
way the world is but simply because this is the way I or my group does things."�
The problem is that no group (that I know of) has the norm of justification
that allows them to do cruel and vicious things simply because it is the
norm of my group.� That reasoning violates the norms of moral justification
of both Chinese and Western communities.� That does not mean Chinese and Western
communities have the same norms, but that neither has Ivanhoe's crude
relativist norm.�
[84] This mistake plagues Chinn's (1997) analysis.�
"all of these ways of seeing the world are equally valid" is not
a judgment that could be made from any of the rival conceptions--all would
find their own more valid than their opponents.� Nor could we make it from
the point of view of 天 tiannature:sky -- which makes
no normative judgments. It does not follow in any way from the Zhuangzi
analysis unless we confuse it with the claim that the content of
our judgment includes a relativity rider.
[85] This is a revisionist reading of the commonplace
contrast of Daoists and Confucians that says Daoist replace 天� tiannature:sky�
with 道 daoguide. They do, but not in that they treat
道 daoguide as a word for a God-creator but that they
dethrone 天� tiannature:sky� as an authority on matters
of value. Only a 道 daoguide can be a source of a
norm or standard.
[86] Perhaps this is the position that Ivanhoe rephrases
as "some deep truth about the world."
[87] See Barry (1995). Chinn (1997, 1998) notices
this implication.
[88] I have been stimulated by reading David Wong
"Zhuangzi on the Dilemma of Value Pluralism" (forthcoming) concerning
the problem of maintaining our moral balance when cognizant of the kind of
relativism Zhuangzi points to. He powerfully and evocatively presents what
he calls "the problem of commitment." In effect, I'm suggesting
here that the problem is an illusion that comes from confusing Zhuangzi's
relativistic skepticism from more familiar undermining of our beliefs about
our way of life (i.e., by positively showing something wrong with it or positively
demonstrating the superiority of something else).�
[89] Implicitly, here, I agree with Wong (1984) (See
fn. 79)that the Daoist justification
of anarchy is a reflection of their weakness as political philosophers. They
did not envision any structural alternative to Confucian authoritarianism.
It is in this sense that Daoism and so-called "Legalism" belong
together. The Fa-jia were starting to work out an alternative conception of
government functioning--though still not an adequate one.
[90] Arguably, Xunzi's response in his Ch. 22 (Rectifying
Names) is equally forced on him.� If anarchy is intolerable, as most Confucians
feel, then the ruler must outlaw philosophy�since it leads to relativism and
skepticism of the purpose of government.
|